Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-17 of 17 documents


1. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

artigos

2. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39
José Barata-Moura

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
3. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39
Marco Sgarbi

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
«Two things fill the mind with ever new and increasing admiration and awe, the more often and steadily reflection is occupied with them: the starry heaven above me and the moral law within me». With these famous words written on paper and inscribed in stone, Immanuel Kant concludes the Critique of Practical Reason. In this paper, I intend to show how this sentence is closely linked with: 1) the kantian doctrine on the sublime and 2) to the foundation of the logic of the irrational in the Critique of Judgement.
4. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39
Fernando Manuel Ferreira da Silva

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
«Die Art, wie er den Mechanismus der Natur mit ihrer Zweckmäßigkeit vereiniget, scheint mir eigentlich den ganzen Geist seines Systems zu enthalten»; This quotation, which originated the present essay, is solely extracted from a letter sent by Hölderlin to Hegel, and yet, it condensates three different approaches from the three Tübingen friends to the problem of Kant’s philosophy of religion and to its possible resolution between 1795 and 1796. From this epistolary dialogue emerges a simultaneous study of Kant, originated by the growing dissension towards the orthodox thought of the Stift. The tuming point - or the maximum cumulative point - of this discordance happens precisely with the discovery of the «spirit of Kant’s System», as a combined explanation of the religious and philosophical phenomena [«Die Art, wie er den Mechanismus der Natur mit ihrer Zweckmässigkeit vereiniget»]. This, I think, is something which the three friends discover gradually and not independently from the concept of «providence», which Kant himself, according to Hölderlin, had used to «attenuate his antinomies», which Hegel uses in his first religious writings and the initial formation of his own philosophy and which Schelling will later explore in his System of Transcendental Idealism. In a word, providence is consensually the comprehension axis between man, God and nature and, thus, the explanatory link between the antinomical poles which regulate human existence. On the other hand, however - this being the aspect I would like to stress - , this decisive moment for a whole generation, for the history of philosophy itself, means the consummation of a new revolutionary perspective born in Kant, a new vision of the absolute and the divine and, therefore, a new way to write philosophy about philosophy, less philosophical than before, to the extent that the new situation of man and his reflection within the problem ultimately destined them - as is the case in the three young philosophers - to silence and death. The final aim of this essay is, therefore, to know what this «last step of philosophy» is and what dies along with it, what such a step may have meant and what it already foretold in terms of the development of philosophy.
5. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39
Vânia Dutra de Azeredo

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper confronts the distinction between an immanent eternity and a transcendent one with David Harvey’s concept of time-space compression, trying to show that this author, from a Nietzschean analysis of his considerations about the post-modem condition, makes use of a traditional conceptual apparatus to evaluate that condition. So we place the Harveyan concept of time-space compression in a transcendent eternity, which is still conformed to the tradition, according to our interpretation of Nietzsche.
6. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39
Ricardo Silva

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper aims to provide an adequate philosophical groundwork to normativity. More specifîcally, the author argues in favor of its axiological nature: from a philosophical point of view, normativity only becomes intelligible if values are taken into account. Therefore values arise as a necessary condition of normativity. Although not sufficient, values are the decisive condition in distinguishing norms from other relations of the same type. The thought of axiologists like Max Scheler and Nicolai Hartmann is discussed even though their theories do not fully explain how norm (ought-to-be) and value interrelate.
7. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39
Ana Falcato

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
As it is well known, the Philosophical Investigations are formally structured as a set of paragraphs numerically sequenced (Part I), and a more arbitrary group of thematic remarks (Part II). In the Prologue and in a justifying way of putting it, Wittgenstein States that: «Thus this book is really only an Album». Taking it as an exhibition of a series of sketches, we can read (or see) the book as a collection of «pictures of thought». However, as I will argue, in a wider understanding of the Philosophical Investigations, the idea of an album has deeper implications than the methodological ones. With a somewhat spenglerian inspiration, the book follows a sort of cultural-transcendental perspective in accordance to the organic model of a philosophical approach to forms of life which have a primary linguistic configuration.
8. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39
Maria José Varandas

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper defends that environmental aesthetics provides a consistent basis for environmental philosophy, whereas aesthetic value plays an important role in the defense and preservation of natural areas. For several environmental philosophers the natural beauty is an inherent part of the ethical concern. Leopold States that “a thing is right when it tends to preserve the integrity, the balance and the beauty of the biotic community”. Notwithstanding, aesthetic value is still not a central issue in the environmental debate. On the other hand, the “positive aesthetics” (Allen Carlson), which is a recent approach that reevaluates “positively” natural beauty in the ethical context, obtains a core of objections. This paper sketches a few arguments defending the contiguity between environmental aesthetics and environmental ethics: (i) the emotional perception of inclusiveness and engagement on the aesthetics appreciation of nature; (ii) the feelings of grace and love to ward nature inherent to the nature’s aesthetic appreciation which according Kant announces the moral feeling; (iii) the ecological knowledge of natural beauty in order to understand the full meaning of it, and that includes some natural entities seen as not beautiful.
9. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39
Francisco Felizol Marques

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In democracy, the people take the place of a single and universal God. Since the first democracy’s modern theorizations there is a tendency to give the people the (not) attributes of a single god. This abstraction of features allows the people to include all the differences and particularities and then universalizes itself as the source and foundation of all power. The people in democracy are not only innate, uncaused, immortal, incorporeal, unextended, are omnipresent, omniscient (or infallible) and omnipotent - negative attributes as well. The people have also virtues that have been established as human, which, because sacralized, sublimated, are negative attributes as well. The only positive feature of the people, to be full age, reveals its functional nature. The voice of the people is the voice of a God. Therefore the single God creates over his voice, the people creates in an election result. In democracy, this voice creates in an infallible way.

recensões

10. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39
João Duarte

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39
José Gomes André

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

notícias de colóquios

12. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39
M. Elena Bentivegna

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
13. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39
Mário André Salvador Carreiro, Rui Manuel de Matos Filipe

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
14. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39
Maribel Sobreira

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

dissertações

15. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39
Bruno Peixe Dias

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
16. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39
Tiago Mesquita Carvalho

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

17. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 39

view |  rights & permissions | cited by