Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-20 of 62 documents


articles

1. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 4
Christopher S. King

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Highlighting a progression of exercises, this paper develops a pedagogical model aimed at giving students tools to deliberate about justice from within the Original Position and to debate the broader goals and limitations of justice as fairness. The approach focuses on the idea of a “distribution” of primary goods without relying on caricatures or being intimidated by the more technical features of the presentation. The series of exercises shows students how to move from more intuitive to less intuitive deliberative situations—a move that depends on seeing a just distribution as a product of a pure procedure. In particular, the exercises show the importance of distinguishing carefully between a distribution and an allocation of goods. Finally, it suggests ways in which we may use the theory to engage with our own distributive practices in democratic societies by focusing on the moral significance of persons as equals.
2. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 4
James Lee

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper will argue for the teaching of component skills in philosophy. We can distinguish between complex and component skills. Component skills bear a kind of constitutive relation to complex skills. We observe this distinction at use in standard pedagogies related to activities like sports, music performance, and mathematics. The central thesis is that devoting pedagogical resources to the development of component skills, especially at introductory levels, promotes better learning outcomes with respect to complex philosophical skills. Aside from defending this thesis, I will also provide a number of examples of activities that can be used to develop component skills.
3. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 4
Jana McAuliffe

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this essay I advocate for the pedagogical value of public philosophy. In public essays, philosophers craft short arguments in clear prose that avoids disciplinary specific technical terms. Such texts are pedagogically valuable both because they teach students philosophical ideas and also because they offer students a template for philosophical argumentation upon which to model their own writing. Here I report on some of the pedagogical practices I have used for teaching public texts to advanced and introductory level undergraduates in order to demonstrate how public philosophy serves as a valuable resource for the teaching of philosophy that can help students develop their capacity for engaged philosophical thinking and the effective communication of philosophical ideas.
4. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 4
Andrew P. Mills

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Reflective journals are characterized by their expressive freedom and their intent that students explicitly connect course material to their own life experiences, emotions, beliefs, and feelings. Drawing on research on the use of reflective journals and on the reflections of students in my philosophy courses, I demonstrate how philosophy professors can use reflective journals as a tool to help their students achieve important learning outcomes. By making philosophy personal for students, reflective journals allow students to practice philosophy as a way of life, achieve important metacognitive outcomes, and (drawing on constructivism in learning theory) increase their knowledge and understanding of course content.
5. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 4
Ian Schnee, Kristi Straus, José M. Guzmán, Ariane Gauvreau

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Teaching through discussion is perhaps the most fundamental pedagogical technique of philosophy. When done well, discussion can promote long-term, durable learning. It supports an active-learning classroom, sparks higher-order cognition, and helps students construct their own understanding of the material. Yet it is often not done well: it is easily dominated by a few students; it can waste time on tangents and minutiae; it can fail to motivate students to prepare adequately; and it is not easily scalable. In this paper we present a technique, the random discussion leader (RDL), which addresses all of these shortcomings of traditional discussion. Qualitative and quantitative evidence from our quasi-experimental study (n = 279) suggests that RDL leads to better preparation, better engagement with the material, more equitable participation, and higher quality discussions. Additionally, we provide a toolkit for instructors interested in trying RDL, showing how the technique can be adapted to various course settings and materials.

book reviews

6. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 4
Zoe Anthony

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
7. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 4
Andrei-Valentin Bacrau

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
8. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 4
Ley David Elliette Cray

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 4
Emily Esch

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
10. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 4
Michael Gifford

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 4
Michael Goldman

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 4
Tim Juvshik

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
13. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 4
Asha Lancaster-Thomas

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
14. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 4
Miriana Maio

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
15. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 4
Antonio L. Sartori

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
16. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 4
Daniel Weltman

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

articles

17. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Benjamin Hole, Monica Janzen, Ramona C. Ilea

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Tragedy feels disempowering and the confluence of tragedies since the beginning of 2020 can overwhelm one’s sense of agency. This paper describes how we use a civic engagement (CE) project to nurture radical hope for our students. Radical hope involves a desire for a positive outcome surpassing understanding, as well as an activity to strive to achieve that outcome despite its uncertainty. Our CE project asks students to identify ethical issues they care about and respond in a fitting way, questioning the assumption that their efforts do not matter, and imagining creative ways to make a difference that are in their power. We scaffold our CE project in order to nurture hopeful possibilities for students by offering real-world, feasible pathways for addressing systemic problems.
18. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
W. John Koolage, Natalie C. Anderson

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this article, we defend the view that problematic epistemological extremism, which presents puzzles for many learners new to philosophy, is a result of earlier learning at the K–12 level. Confirming this hunch serves as a way of locating the problem and suggesting that recent learning interventions proposed by Christopher Edelman (2021) and Galen Barry (2022) are on the right track. Further, we offer that this extremism is plausibly described as what Miranda Fricker (2007) calls an epistemic injustice. This suggests that disrupting the problem is a boon for learners, the discipline, and good citizenship. In our discussion we introduce work by Derek Muller suggesting that it is important to address the misconceptions involved in epistemological extremism (and its precursors) lest we simply reinforce these problematic misconceptions for the worse—inhibiting student learning, reproducing challenges to good citizenship, and leading to a discounting of many ways of knowing.
19. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Menno van Calcar

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Teaching philosophy online in secondary schools differs from offline teaching. The explanations usually offered for this difference show the cognitivist assumptions of mainstream pre-university philosophy education, meaning that philosophy education assumes that the aim of its practice is the enhancement of internal mental abilities. This paper argues that this view of the goal of education is unwarranted and unnecessarily restrictive, and that it implies an undesirable dichotomy between learning to be competent and being competent. An alternative, based on ecological and enactive views of cognition, is presented as a better conception of philosophical cognitive competence in general, and of the difference between offline and online teaching in particular. This alternative suggests that the difference resembles the difference between life in a zoo and life in the jungle, and that we should teach pupils to do wild philosophy.
20. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Hasko von Kriegstein

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
At or near the beginning of many textbooks and syllabi in applied or professional ethics is a unit on philosophical moral theories (such as utilitarianism, deontology, and virtue ethics). However, teaching such theories is of questionable value in this context. This article introduces the moral vocabulary approach. Instead of burdening students with complex ethical theories, they are introduced to the logic of elementary moral concepts. This avoids many of the drawbacks of teaching ethical theories, while preserving the benefit of equipping students with the conceptual tools they need to critically analyse ethical issues.