|
1.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2022 >
Issue: 63
Call for Paper for Special Issue in Arguments in Philosophy of Religion
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
2.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2022 >
Issue: 63
Graham Oppy
Graham Oppy
Good Argument
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
According to the common conception of argument, the virtues of arguments turn, in part, on the virtues of assertion of their premises. I suggest that, on plausible Gricean assumptions about cooperative conversation, the common conception yields the claim that it is never appropriate to advance arguments in cooperative conversations. But that claim is absurd! Holding on to the Gricean assumptions, I reject the common conception of argument in favour of an alternative conception, on which all that matters, as far as premises go, for the virtue of arguments, is whether those premises belong to the arguments’ targets: interlocutors’ beliefs, theories, etc.
According to the common conception of argument, the virtues of arguments turn, in part, on the virtues of assertion of their premises. I suggest that, on plausible Gricean assumptions about cooperative conversation, the common conception yields the claim that it is never appropriate to advance arguments in cooperative conversations. But that claim is absurd! Holding on to the Gricean assumptions, I reject the common conception of argument in favour of an alternative conception, on which all that matters, as far as premises go, for the virtue of arguments, is whether those premises belong to the arguments’ targets: interlocutors’ beliefs, theories, etc.
|
|
|
3.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2022 >
Issue: 63
蔡岳璋
Yueh-chang Tsai
Anti-intellectual? or Knowledge By Embodiment? Hints from “The Butcher’s Knife”
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
一般論及道家對於知識的態度,通常認為道家並不賦予知識以本體論意 義上的正面價值與意義。然而,一個顯而易見的事實是,與身體有關的技藝 寓言,卻頻繁的出現在《莊子》文本之中。這似乎意味著,雖然知識所能指 涉的並非最高的境界,卻是生命流行所不可或缺的。藉由無懈可擊的技藝展 演,莊子無疑肯定知識具有不容越次躐等的中介性質。若果以心齋、坐忘為 核心的傳統心性論哲學,關注的焦點是作為主體之我與作為客體的世界的物 我兩忘、主客合一、虛靜觀照的(藝術)精神境界。那麼,以身體為中心(以 氣為體)的職工達人的技藝哲學,強調的則是以具體的技藝實踐細節(心、 手、器、物)的相互關聯性,及其彼此互援的沉浸式體驗,作為在世活動的 整體範式。
Generally speaking, when it comes to Taoism’s attitude toward knowledge, people usually think that Taoism doesn’t grant knowledge positive value and meanings. However, it is an obvious fact that artistry fables related to bodies and knowledge appear frequently in works of Zhuangzi. It seems that even though knowledge doesn’t always involve the highest level, it is absolutely necessary in life. Through these impeccable performances of techniques, undoubtedly, Zhuangzi confirms knowledge occupies an intermediary stage that can’t be ignored. The philosophy of these labor professions of artistry, centered on bodies, (Qi as bodies) emphasizes the interconnection between practicing details of movements (Hearts, Hands, Tools, Objects) and immersive experiences that support each other, and uses it as the model of being alive in the world.
|
|
|
4.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2022 >
Issue: 63
陳康寧
Kang-Lin Tan
From Zhuangzi’s “Yang Sheng Zhu” to the Ethical Subject of Tai Chi: Exploring a Response to the Contemporary Crisis of Subjectivity
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
在後現代思潮的衝擊下,啟蒙時代的主體觀受到很大的挑戰。然而,過 於強調主體,固然容易造成對他者的壓迫,形成同質化的暴力;但主張去主 體,又往往導致生命虛無與實踐的乏力,難以確立倫理責任,畢竟,主體能 動性是構成責任的先決條件。本文主張,面對當代的主體性危機,《莊子》 的「養生主」提供了嶄新的視野,能夠為當代奠立更合宜的主體觀。「養生 主」作為一個重要的哲學概念,不只是保養身體、安頓心靈而已,還指向了 一種經營倫理關係(養親)的生命人格。「養生主」以氣化與工夫修養為關 鍵的實踐過程,所成就的倫理主體,會對他者的差異化保持開放,不再是只 強調同一的主體。然而,這樣的工夫如何落實在生活脈絡裡,也是一個重要 問題。本文以太極拳這門具有古典文化意涵的武術作為考察,透過《莊子》 「養生主」的概念來詮釋太極武術中的「懂勁」、「神明」、「完整一氣」、「捨 己從人」、「物來順應」等的虛化工夫所成就的倫理主體,同時以「極柔軟,然後能極堅剛」來說明這樣的虛化工夫,不僅僅是「去主體化」,同時也是 「主體化」的實踐歷程。換言之,在「去主體化」與「主體化」的交織下所 形成的倫理主體,可視為對當代主體危機的一種回應可能
Under the impact of the post-modern trend of ideas, the concept of subjectivity in the Enlightenment era has been greatly challenged. While the excessive emphasis on the subject may easily lead to the oppression of others and the formation of violence of homogenization, advocating de-subjectivation tends to lead to the emptiness of life and the weakness of practice. Moreover, it becomes difficult to establish ethical responsibility. After all, the subject is a prerequisite for responsibility. This study suggests that when faced with the contemporary crisis of subjectivity, Zhuangzi’s “Yang Sheng Zhu”(養生主) provides a brand-new perspective which can create a more appropriate concept of subjectivity for the contemporary era. As an important philosophical concept, “Yang Sheng Zhu” is not limited to maintaining physical and spiritual health but also points to a personality of life that manages an ethical relationship (caring for relatives). “Yang Sheng Zhu” is a practical process using Qi(氣) and mind cultivation as the key, and the ethical subject achieved by this practice will remain open to the differences of others. This practice no longer only emphasizes the sameness of the subject. However, how to implement such a practice in the context of life is also an important issue. This study probes into Tai Chi, a martial art with classical cultural connotations, and uses the concept of Zhuangzi’s “Yang Sheng Zhu” to interpret the ethical subject achieved by the invisible practice of “understanding of power,” “shenming,” “complete Qi,” “sacrificing oneself to serve others,” and “accepting every encounter” in Tai Chi. This study also uses “extremely soft, and then extremely rigid” to explain that such an invisible practice is not only “de-subjectivation” but also the realization of “subjectivation.” In other words, the ethical subject formed under the interweaving of “de-subjectivation” and “subjectivation” can be regarded as a possible response to the contemporary crisis of subjectivity.
|
|
|
|
5.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2022 >
Issue: 63
夏逸平
Yi-Ping Xia
A Review of Christian J. Emden’s Nietzsche’s Naturalism. Philosophy and the Life Sciences in the Nineteenth Century
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
尼采的自然主義或者尼采作為自然主義者可以說是過去二十年英美尼 采學界最為熱門的研究論題之一,而在所有相關作品中,Christian Emden 的《尼采的自然主義》則憑藉其出色的歷史脈絡化工作以及對哲學問題的敏 銳關注而成為尼采研究領域不可忽略的著作。在書中,Emden 在十九世紀早 期新康德主義以及生命科學的脈絡下重構了尼采的自然主義,並認為尼采的 系譜學提供了對規範性的一個自然歷史的詮釋。本文將首先簡介在英美以及 德國學界所展開的對尼采自然主義詮釋的爭論,接著概覽Emden 一書的章 節內容,隨後介紹以及評論此書的核心觀點,最後則以對當代尼采研究的簡 短反思作為結論
Nietzsche’s naturalism or Nietzsche as a naturalist could be regarded as one of the hottest research topics in Anglo-American Nietzsche studies in the past twenty years. Of all the related works, Christian Emden’s Nietzsche’s Naturalism is indispensable in the field of Nietzsche studies for its excellent historical contextualization and keen attention to philosophical problems. In this book, he reconstructs Nietzsche’s philosophical naturalism in the context of early neo-Kantianism and the life sciences in the nineteenth century and interprets Nietzsche’s genealogy as a philosophical critique that delivers a natural history of normativity. This review will begin with a brief introduction of the debate around Nietzsche’s naturalism in Anglo-American and German scholarship, then give an overview of the chapters in Emden’s book. After introducing and commenting on Emden’s core ideas, it will conclude with a brief reflection on contemporary Nietzsche studies.
|
|
|
6.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2022 >
Issue: 63
楊德立
Tak-lap Yeung
A Critique from an Enlightenment Humanist: A Review of Tze-wan Kwan’s The Way betwixt Being and Man: On Heidegger’s Philosophical Detours
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
關子尹《徘徊於天人之際:海德格的哲學思路》共收十一篇長論文,而 最引人注目的,是三篇從未發表的長文。三篇內容皆論及海德格整個思想生 涯,但就問題意識而言,則偏重海氏後期旨趣,而且內容具延續性,值得一 拼閱讀及討論。 通過對新三篇的闡釋可見,此書並非單從釋義的角度來談論海德格哲 學。經過全書梳理各種在海德格哲學中極為斑駁甚至跡近奧密的主題及義理 後,其理論後果得以客觀且具體地呈現眼前,而作者則對此作出了極為全 面、深刻且嚴厲的批判。對海德格的整體批評,主要為兩點:一,海氏對主 體性的批判過於嚴苛,連帶對個人能動性所構成的個人責任亦過於輕視; 二,海氏對人類理性過於不信任。這兩要點遍佈全書,在某些篇章特別明確, 而這些批評,實立足於一個具有現代啟蒙精神的人文主義者的立場之上。
Tze-wan Kwan’s The Way betwixt Being and Man: On Heidegger’s Philosophical Detours contains a total of eleven long essays, the most notable of which are the three long essays that have never been published. All three articles deal with Heidegger’s entire intellectual career, but in terms of philosophical orientation, they focus mainly on Heidegger’s later interests. Therefore, they are worth reading and discussing as a whole because of the continuity in content. Through the exposition of the three new essays, it can be seen that this book does not discuss Heidegger’s philosophy merely for the purpose of interpreting his concepts and statements. After sorting out the various themes and meanings in Heidegger’s philosophy, which are extremely diverse and even close to esoteric, the theoretical consequences are revealed concretely and objectively, and, in addition, the author provides an extremely comprehensive, profound, and severe critique of them. The overall criticism of Heidegger is mainly about two points: first, Heidegger’s criticism of subjectivity is too strict and, consequently, he underestimates the personal responsibility constituted by individual spontaneity; second, Heidegger is too distrustful of human reason. These two points, while more explicitly stated in some chapters, animate the whole book. I argue that the criticism comes from the perspective of a humanist with the spirit of modern enlightenment.
|
|
|
|
7.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2021 >
Issue: 62
熊偉均
Wei-Chun Hsiung
The Virtuous Conduct “Not Forming Inwardly”
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
本文之研究目標是試圖解決郭店竹簡《五行》首章之詮釋困難,並以竹簡《五行》自身的內容做為首要的證據來源。首先,筆者整理帛書派、竹簡派與調和派對首章爭議的不同見解,並點出竹簡派導致詮釋困難的思維架構;接著釐清竹簡《五行》「德之行」、「行」與「德」三者之別,以及考察竹簡《五行》「形」與「聖」之用例,發掘「聖」兼具兩種意涵之「形」,據此為竹簡《五行》首章提供更為全面且融貫之詮釋:作為最高意義的「聖」,必然在「形於內」的基礎上,兼具了內在轉化層面「形於無形」與人倫教化層面「形於眾人」此雙重意義。竹簡《五行》首章據此主張唯有「聖」無論「形於內」或「不形於內」皆可以稱為「德之行」,並確立「聖」具備超越「仁義禮智」四者的獨特地位。
This paper aims at solving the interpretive problem in the first chapter of Wu Xing of Guodian bamboo texts, majorly based on the text itself. It starts by categorizing different interpretations into three groups (the for-silk-texts, the for-bamboo-texts, and the reconciliatory), and points out the thinking patterns which have led the for-bamboo-texts to misinterpretation. It also analyzes the distinction among the virtuous conduct (dezhixing), conduct (xing), and virtue (de), and reexamines usages of the forming (xing) and sageness (sheng) of the Wu Xing to conclude that the concept of sageness includes two different meanings of forming. Therefore, the reason why the conduct of sageness should be regarded as virtuous conduct regardless of whether or not it forms “inwardly” is that the sageness, the supreme virtue, possesses both “imperceivable forming” (personal self-cultivation and transformation) and “societal forming” (interpersonal enlightenment and amelioration), which establishes the virtue of sageness in a unique position superior to the four cardinal virtues.
|
|
|
8.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2021 >
Issue: 62
朱弘道
Hung-Tao Chu
Reexamination of the Metaphor of “Faggots” and “Fire” in Yang Sheng Zhu
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
以往研究對於《莊子•養生主》中「指窮於為薪,火傳也,不知其盡也」一句的詮釋基本上可分為兩種:其一是在標舉出形、神的對立作為詮釋工具,分別以此兩者比喻薪火,藉此提出「重神養神」的養生方針;其二則是以「事物自然地流轉變化」為分析脈絡,強調「火」的無窮無盡,並提出「勿使形體的存亡影響己心」的看法。筆者認為,以上兩詮釋各有其理據,亦有其源遠流長之歷史脈絡,因此才為學界所接受。然筆者認為,以往詮釋中,在通假字的使用、目標域與來源域的連結及字義解釋等處,尚有幾項值得討論的面向。本文將嘗試以高亨與劉武的注本作為基礎,轉換以往將「薪火之喻」作「正面」詮釋的共通點,而將其解釋為不應發生的「負面」情況。並嘗試指出,此詮釋除可在文本找到相應之說,亦能夠於以上癥結點給出回應,因此具有其獨特之價值。
This paper offers a new interpretation of the following Zhuangzi fragment: “What we can point to are the faggots that have been consumed; but the fire is transmitted (elsewhere), and we know not that it is over and ended” (Yang Sheng Zhu, chapter 3). There are two commonly accepted interpretations. One points out the opposition of form (xing 形) and spirit (shen 神) and suggests taking care of and preserving spirit as a regimen. The other interpretation focuses on the change of everything and the endlessness of fire and suggests that one’s mind should not be affected by the living or dying of things. Both interpretations have a long pedigree and enjoy their own internal support. However, in both interpretations, there are remaining issues related to the use of phonetic loan characters, the connection between source and target domains in the metaphors used, and the interpretation of some word meanings. On the basis of the commentaries of Gao Heng and Liu Wu, I attempt to develop an alternative interpretation. While both of the interpretations introduced above regard faggot and fire as positive metaphors, I instead argue that these metaphors portray negative situations that should be avoided. This novel interpretation has its own unique value because it finds support in Zhuangzi and because it meets the problems of the former two interpretations.
|
|
|
9.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2021 >
Issue: 62
鍾振宇
Chen-Yu Chung
The Paradox of Non-Usefulness and Usefulness
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
海德格在二次大戰德國戰敗之日(1945 年5 月8 日),寫了一篇對話式文章紀念此一日子,文章區分兩種用:無用與有用,最後引用了莊惠對話,提出德國要成為「無用的民族」以引領未來世界。海德格認為大戰是現代性擴張精神的結果,而其中最關鍵的就是「有用」的思考與世界觀。本文將莊惠兩種存有論的重點放在「用」的兩種差異上,視莊子為「無用的存有論」,視惠施為「有用的存有論」。這點除了文本根據外,更具有當代意義。透過海德格對於兩種用的區分,筆者試圖闡發莊惠辯論的當代意義。
At the time when Germany was defeated in the World War 2 (May 8, 1945), Heidegger wrote a dialogic essay to memorize the event. In the essay he differentiated two kinds of usefulness: non-Usefulness and usefulness. What merits our attention is that at the end of the essay he quoted the conversation between Zhuangzi and Huishi and proposed that Germany be “the nationality of non-usefulness” so as to lead the world in the future. For him the War resulted from the spirit of expansion of which ideology and worldview of “usefulness” lies at the heart. It is against such a background that this essay attempts to construct an account of Zhuangzi’s and Huishi’s ontologies by differentiating their views on “usefulness”, whereby Zhuangzi is read to represent “the ontology of non-usefulness” and Huishi to stand for “the ontology of usefulness”. Viewed in light of Heidegger’s differentiation of two kinds of “usefulness”, the essay hopes to explicate the contemporary significance of the dispute between Zhuangzi and Huishi, particularly Huishi’s emphasis on usefulness which I suggest can be related to the modern pursuit of usefulness.
|
|
|
10.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2021 >
Issue: 62
佐藤將之
Masayuki Sato
The Birth of Chinese Philosophy in Meiji Japan
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
本文是為了闡明目前學界所稱呼「中國哲學」或「東洋哲學」的學術領域在明治時期的日本如何誕生、如何形成之一番試論。所謂「中國哲學」這樣學術領域是以「哲學」這樣的概念和學科之引進為契機而形成,並且此契機的磁石場是當時剛創立的東京大學。本文經過其創立時期教授與中國哲學相關內容的課程之費諾羅薩(Ernest F. Fenollosa)、井上哲次郎以及島田重禮三位的上課內容之分析,勾勒出江戶時代以來經學或儒學的思想內容由「哲學」的分析框架來獲得新的思想涵義之過程。如此,在德川時代原來被視為經學上的內容逐漸轉換成「人格修養」、「國民道德」等具備近代特質的倫理主張。孔孟等經學上的聖人以及戰國諸子也皆變成了「哲學家」。
This article attempts to elucidate the origin and formation of the “Chinese philosophy” or “Oriental philosophy” as an academic field which took form during the Meiji Era of Japan. The academic field called “Chinese philosophy” originated mainly from the incorporation of the discipline of philosophy into Tokyo University during the 1870s. The main scholars who contributed to the formation of this scholarly field were Ernest Fenollosa, Inoue Tetsujirō, and Shimada Chōrei. Fenollosa was the first teacher who taught the contents of Chinese thought from the viewpoint of philosophy. Inoue Tetsujirō was also the first instructor who took charge of the seminar under the title of “Oriental philosophy” in which he compared the “philosophical significance” of those early Chinese thinkers with those of their counterparts in the Western philosophical tradition. Shimada, succeeding Inoue, was another pioneer because he first taught the whole history of Chinese thought from the ancient to the Manchurian period, though Shimada himself had not received philosophy education in his youth. Their seminars have strengthened the philosophical image of traditional Chinese thinkers, and as a result, those thinkers have been all considered to be “philosophers” by the time of the early twentieth century. It was by this re-interpretation of the significance of traditional thought, especially from the perspective of ethics, that the contents of Confucian canonical studies of the Tokugawa period have been transformed into a new ideological ground for advocating the necessity of self-cultivation and so-called “national morality” in the following Taishō and Shōwa periods.
|
|
|
11.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2021 >
Issue: 61
Jerry J. Yang
楊景德
對羅森陶反意識本有主義論證之回應
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Rosenthal argues that if consciousness is seen as intrinsic, it will appear to be simple and unanalyzable, and therefore not amenable to scientific explanation, which requires a relational structure involving an extrinsic property of the mind. I shall first criticize Rosenthal's argument against intrinsicalism by way of conceptual analysis. I shall then examine three of his arguments against the intrinsic view of consciousness: the argument from the distinction between transitive and intransitive consciousness, the argument from reporting and expressing, and the argument of the individuation of mental states. I suggest that the content of a mental state can be considered to be an information space, which will allow for an explanation of consciousness. My rejection of Rosenthal's position relies on distinguishing two different forms of intrinsicalism: with and without self-representation. We shall find that both versions have explanatory traction from a naturalistic perspective.
羅森陶指出若意識被當作一種本有性質,它就會是單純與不可分析的,並且因此無法提供科學性的說明,因為科學性說明要求一種具有心靈的外在性質的關係式架構。我首先從概念分析的角度批評羅森陶反本有主義的論證。接著,逐一檢視羅森陶三個反本有主義的論證:及物與非及物意識區分的論證、報告與表達的論證,與個別化心靈狀態的論證。我建議將單一心靈狀態的內容視為一個訊息空間,可以用之來說明意識。我依據兩種不同型態的本有主義來反對羅森陶的立場:一種是包含自我表徵,另一種則不包含。我們將會發現這兩種類型的理論,在自然主義的視角下都擁有解釋的力量。
|
|
|
12.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2021 >
Issue: 61
劉吉宴
Chi Yen Liu
Two Criteria of Reasonable Inferences
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
亞當斯和史東內克在傳統的有效性觀點之外,對指示條件句的推論提出了合理性這樣的概念,並對這樣的概念提出了兩個不同的準則。本文從可斷說性的概念分別來對兩者提出形式上的刻畫,以檢視這兩者的關係。本文把亞當斯支持的準則稱為「可斷說性的證成性」,而把史東內克支持的準則稱為「嚴格的證成性」,並認為這兩個準則可以幫助我們釐清條件句推論中的爭議。本文用這兩個準則來重新分析麥基對肯定前件律所提出的反例,試圖說明為何麥基提出的是一個可斷說證成性的反例,而不是嚴格證成性的反例。接著,本文對這個現象提出一個診斷,說明為何這兩個準則只會在條件句的推論中產生實質的分歧。最後,本文論證可斷說性的證成性太過於嚴格而難以成立,主張嚴格的證成性才是一個較好的準則。
Validity is an orthodox way to distinguish between good and bad inferences, which says that when inferences are valid, we can derive true conclusions from true premises. But when inferences involve conditionals, validity does not seem to be a good criterion. Unsatisfied with the traditional view of validity, Adams(1965) and Stalnaker(1975) propose their modified criteria, which are called “reasonable inference” in this paper, to evaluate inferences involving conditionals. In this paper, Adams’ criterion is called “justification of assertibility”, which can derive a highly assertible conclusion from highly assertible premises. Stalnaker’s criterion is called “justification of strictness” in this paper, which can derive a strictly assertible conclusion from strictly assertible premises. This paper examines these two criteria and their consequences. First, by reexamining McGee’s(1985) counterexample to modus ponens, I argue that McGee’s example is an assertibility-justified but not a strictness-justified counterexample to modus ponens. Second, I explain why these two criteria have such a substantial divergence when inferences have conditional conclusions. Third, if my diagnosis is correct and complicated conditionals are allowed in inferences, then the justification of assertibility is too rigid to be satisfied. I conclude that the justification of strictness is a better criterionthan the justification of assertibility.
|
|
|
13.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2021 >
Issue: 61
Tsung-Hsing Ho
何宗興
如何在中文裡定位疼痛
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Some philosophers argue that pain is an object located in bodily parts because the locative form of pain report is permissible in English. To examine this argument, Liu and Klein recently argue that the linguistic argument cannot work because the locative form is impermissible in Mandarin. They are wrong, however. I demonstrate that the locative form in Mandarin is not only permissible but also common.
有些哲學家主張疼痛是一種處於身體部位的對象,理由是英文可以用定位句式說明疼痛是允許的。最近,Liu 與Klein 檢視中文對於說明疼痛的用法,指出中文不允許用定位句式說明疼痛。然而,我主張他們是錯的,我提供實例來論證如何在中文裡使用定位句式來說明疼痛。
|
|
|
14.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2020 >
Issue: 60
許瑞娟
Jui-Chuan Hsu
An Interpretation of Guo Xiang’s Commentary on Zhuangzi
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
本文從兩方面重新思考郭象「逍遙」的意涵:首先,重新梳理、詮釋郭象《莊子注》;其次,試圖從高達美哲學詮釋學的重要概念分析郭象「逍遙」思想,挖掘郭象玄學的深層意蘊。郭象將自己的思想融入《莊子》中,提出一個人人皆有逍遙可能的理論,前提是人們必須忘掉性分之外者和慾念,接著要實現性分之內的部分,合此二者才是郭象所稱的逍遙。而聖王不將自己的慾念強加於民,因此能夠能引導眾人同獲逍遙。郭象玄學結合高深玄妙理論與現實應用,使得逍遙成為不論聖凡皆可奉行的境界,在這點上,郭象對道家思想盛行於魏晉功不可沒。
The article rethinks the meaning of “Xiaoyao” in Guo Xiang’s philosophy. First, I provide a novel interpretation of Guo Xiang’s Commentary on Zhuangzi. Then, I analyze his Commentary by applying key concepts in Hans-Georg Gadamer’s philosophical hermeneutics. Guo Xiang incorporated Zhuangzi’s philosophy into his own. He believes that every individual can achieve “Xiaoyao,” but only if each person forgets both what is beyond the reach of one’s nature and desires not belonging to oneself. The Sage King does not impose his own ideas on the people, and thus he guides the people to achieve the state of “Xiaoyao.” Guo Xiang’s philosophy, by demonstrating that everyone can achieve “Xiaoyao” in articulating how the abstract reasoning in Zhuangzi has practical application, greatly contributed to the popularity of Taoist Philosophy.
|
|
|
15.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2020 >
Issue: 60
黃崇修
Chung-Hsiu Huang
The Practical Significance of Cheng Yi’s Concept of “Yi and Li”: Interpreting “Cultivation of Qi and Accumulation of Yi” from the Perspective of the Heaven-Man Relationship
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
本文以朱子認同程伊川「不認義理為不仁」一段話作為問題意識開端,試圖透過對伊川義理的實踐性還原以鋪展伊川義理概念之深層意涵。因此筆者首先自問人為什麼不認義理就是不仁?此處所言義理是在什麼立場下與仁有關?如果與仁有關;義與理又是怎樣的邏輯關係而形成其道德實踐上的價值?針對以上諸問,本文一方面從縱貫面針對孔孟對「義」概念的解讀,從而釐清仁與義在孔孟思想中所具有之定位,另一方面在此基礎下,筆者橫向地就伊川理學背景,也就是周敦頤、張載、明道等師友言說中進行探究,繼而在這些宋代儒學建構過程線索中,找到伊川繼承先秦仁義思想特色與轉進軌跡。透過以上二階段之爬梳,本文聚焦伊川對孟子集義養氣之詮釋形式,試圖在其言說中看到伊川天人思想的特色。也就是說,即便伊川強調理一分殊而形成日後朱子理氣論之重要發展,但在宇宙論視野下,伊川思維結構中亦可能與周敦頤、張載一樣具有《管子》天仁地義思維模式之可能。因此筆者第四節中以「天仁地義」視野,試圖透視伊川義理概念在天仁之普遍性原則下,如何開展出一套地義之個體化原則。而此研究成果,將可回應韋政通先生質疑明道仁學消融主客關係從而學理上缺乏犧牲承擔、捨身取義之實踐問題。同時透過此次研究,我們發現到伊川所強調的義理概念的確能夠成為補充詮釋明道仁學道德實踐力之關鍵因素。此成果對於近年筆者探討「中正仁義」定止工夫之際,給予完整而厚實之系統連結。
Zhu Xi, remarkably, approved of Cheng Yi’s saying, “it is considered not benevolent (仁, “ren”) if one does not acknowledge justice (義, “yi”) and reason (理, “li”).” The purpose of this paper is to understand their agreement by explicating the deeper meaning of Cheng Yi’s concept of “yi and li” by reflecting on the practical aspects of this concept. Why is it not considered benevolent if one did not acknowledge yi and li? What sort of yi and li relates to ren? And finally, in their relation to ren, how do yi and li relate to one another to be morally significant?This paper will first interpret the notion of yi in Confucius and Mencius to clarify its relation to ren. Then, on this basis, it will examine the sayings of Cheng Yi’s neo-Confucian comtemporaries, in particular, the arguments of Zhou Dun-Yi, Zhang Zai, Cheng Hao, and Cheng Yi’s other teachers and friends. The purpose is to clarify, in the larger context of the development of neo-Confucianism, what Cheng Yi inherited from Pre-Qin thought on ren and yi, and what he transformed and elaborated.After the above preparation, this paper will discuss Cheng Yi’s interpretation of Mencius’ “cultivation of qi ( 氣, “energy” ) and the accumulation of yi” because the peculiarity of Cheng Yi’s theory of the Heaven-Man relationship comes to light in that interpretation. In other words, although Cheng Yi emphasized one principle with many manifestations which influenced the development of Zhu Xi’s doctrine of li and qi, from the perspective of cosmology, Cheng Yi’s framework, like Zhou Dun-Yi and Zhang Zai, also contains the potential of thinking Heaven as benevolent and humans as having the character of yi (i.e. the idea in Guanzi). Section four thus entertains this possibility and explores how Cheng Yi’s concept of “yi and li” can be articulated in terms of actualizing an individual principle of yi on earth with the universal principle of ren in Heaven in the background.The results of this study can address Wei Zheng-Tong’s critique that Cheng Hao’s doctrine of benevolence, in cancelling the subject-object relationship, neglects the practical question of when to sacrifice one’s life for the sake of yi. At the same time, “yi and li” in Cheng Yi crucially supplements and strengthens the understanding of how Cheng Hao’s doctrine of ren is effective as moral practice. This result provides the pivotal link that shows the systematic coherence of the samadhi skills “zhong-zheng(中正, “moderation”), ren, and yi.”
|
|
|
16.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2020 >
Issue: 60
陳士誠
Shih-Chen Chen
Lu Xiang-Shan on Human Good and Evil by the Self of Two Minds in One
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
本文乃處理象山二心為一之說,以發掘其倫理學意涵及其哲學史根源。二心即是道心與人心;而所謂為一,乃表二心間之統一。依唐君毅之詮釋,視之為同一心之或升或降即表此統一;其次乃依象山文本,筆者視這統一乃表示為決意於或順或逆其本心間的人自我之概念,因而所謂順逆本心即只是人自我之心意識中的兩端緒而已。合此,人自我若順其本心即是其心之上升;反之,若違逆之,則是同一心之下降;在這自我概念下,即能說明人之道德規範與歸責之可能性。此本心與人心之分別,乃是對其概念進行先驗分析而至者,以便能揭示本心概念之特質。但此本心概念並未涵蓋人道德意識之整全,而只這整全中的一部分,因這概念未蘊含犯惡之可能性,所以未能說明犯惡者自身及對其惡之可能歸責。而這人自我之概念所表者乃其心意識之兩端,這才表道德意識之整全:本心是我的本心,我亦是那犯惡者,由是,這自我乃是善惡之可能性之最高主體。以上之分析乃在象山所引用的孟子文本中所建立者,也即是,象山二心為一之說,不論其倫理學意涵抑或其哲學史根源,乃藉孟子學之連結中所達至者。
In this paper I discuss Xiangshan’s unity of two minds in order to explore its ethical implications and the roots of its philosophical history. The two minds mean Dao mind and human mind, and the so-called one mind is the unity of the two. And this unity in my paper is regarded as the one-mind’s rise or fall by the interpretation of Tang Junyi(唐君毅), and as a concept of self to combine two minds in according to Xiangshan’s text, the unity is a self who makes a decision for or against his original mind, thus it is two beginnings of the same mind. In a word, the mind rises when the self’s decision conforms with his original mind, and the same mind falls when his decision violates it. In according to the concept of self the possibility of human’s moral norm and responsibility can be explained. The distinction between the two minds is established by a transcendental analysis of their respective conceptual content, and the point is to reveal the character of original mind. But the concept of original mind doesn’t demonstrate the whole but only a part of moral consciousness, because it doesn’t imply the possibility of evil and thus fails to explain the concept of evildoer and the possible responsibility for his evil. The concept of the self indicates the two beginnings of the human consciousness and as such constitute the whole of moral consciousness: the original mind is mine, and I am also the evildoer, thus the self is nothing but the ultimate subject for the possibility of good and evil. The above analysis is based on the Mencius text quoted by Xiangshan. That is, Xiangshan’s two minds in one, in both its ethical implications and philosophical history, is dependent on his interpretation of Mencius text.
|
|
|
17.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2020 >
Issue: 60
黃文宏
Wen-Hong Huang
On Zeng Tian-Zong’s “Aporia of the Knowledge of Ideal of Truth”
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
本文處理曾天從在其所謂的「理念的真理認識」或「哲學認識」中,所遭遇到的三個難題,並試著根據他所提供的解決線索與保證,來為這些難題給出一個可能的解答。在筆者看來,這三個難題並不真的是難題,但是透過對「理念的真理認識」的這三個難題的思考,可以讓我們更了解曾天從的理念的真理認識的型態,以及其真理論的哲學體系的內容與方向。
This article examines three aporias (difficult problems) encountered by Zeng Tian-Zong (1910-2007) in his notion “Knowledge of Ideal of Truth” or “Philosophical Knowledge”, and proposes a possible answer to these problems based on the clues and guarantees he provides. On the reading proposed here, while these problems turn out to not be genuine difficulties, examination of these aporias in his knowledge of the ideal of truth, better elucidates the nature of his “Knowledge of Ideal of Truth” as well as the content and direction of his philosophical system of Aletheiology.
|
|
|
|
18.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2020 >
Issue: 60
楊德立
Tak-lap Yeung
Interpretation and evaluation
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Rolf-Peter Horstmann 近作《康德之想像力》(Kant’s Power of Imagination),是針對「想像力」在康德學統下備受忽視的情況而作。這部102 頁的著作,仔細分析了《純粹理性批判》和《判斷力批判》中與想像力相關的內容,意圖從內部理順康德的想像力理論,並論證想像力在建構認知對象過程裡的獨特貢獻。他提出了「建構認知對象的兩階段模式」,闡明想像力在認知過程中獨一無二的功能與位置,並在此基礎上論證想像力是一種獨立、自足的認知能力。由於想像力是一種獨立認知能力,因此至少在理論哲學和知識論脈絡下,康德學者沒有忽視想像力的理由。
Rolf-Peter Horstmann’s recent work, Kant's Power of Imagination, is a response to the neglect of “the power of imagination” in the Kantian circle. In this 102-page book, Horstmann analyzes passages relevant to imagination in Critique of Pure Reason and Critique of Judgment in detail, with the aim of making Kant’s theory of imagination coherent. He argues for the unique contribution of imagination in the context of the constitution of cognitive objects. Horstmann proposes a “two-stage model of constructing cognitive objects” in his examination of the irreplaceable function and special position of imagination in the cognitive process, and from this, he argues that imagination is an independent, self-standing cognitive faculty. Since imagination is an independent cognitive ability, at least in the context of theoretical philosophy and epistemology, Kant scholars have no reason to ignore it.
|
|
|
|
19.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2020 >
Issue: 59
林建德
Chien-Te Lin
A Philosophical Reflection on Traditional Pan Jiao
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
現代化客觀的佛教學術研究,易於挑戰乃至否定傳統佛教既有觀點,如不承認佛經皆佛親說(包括「大乘非佛說」),各式的「判教」在史學考證下亦難有立足之地,天台五時判教即是一例。本文試著對此作進一步探討:首先,說明信仰與學術兩種立場的對峙;其次,學術研究雖在知識層次占了上風,但僅能視為是「一種」理解而非「唯一」觀點;第三,佛法之「宗教性」 重於以方便善巧引渡不同根機眾生,如「五時」的「時」除了「時間順序」 外或也指「時節因緣」;第四,傳統判教仍具有意義,背有亦有一套信仰邏輯以建立自宗合理性基礎;第五,除了以正誤、真偽評斷,「權實」應是更理想的評價語彙。最後,對於佛教史理解,或可藉「多重佛史」持多元開放態度而非定於一說。如此,以「歷史之錯誤」斷言傳統判教,就客觀學術雖言之成理,但就信仰實踐而言卻是「宗教之正確」,所以即便是「錯誤」也會是「美麗的錯誤」。
It is easy for modern academic research to challenge and even reject the traditional views of Buddhism. The denial of certain sutras, and also the rejection of Mahayana Buddhism, are cases in point. Various Pan Jiao (判教, “doctrinal classifications”) are untenable under the inspection of historical and philological study; Wu Shi Jiao Pan in Tiantai Buddhism is an instance. This article attempts to present six points to further explore this. First, I argue that there is certainly a conflict between the orientation of academic research and the practice of faith. Second, in terms of level of knowledge, while the academic approach has the upper hand, it is not the sole valid perspective for understanding Buddhism. Third, the religiosity of Dharma is concerned with facilitating the extradition of different humans. In this sense, the timing in the “five-stage distinction” emphasizes causes and conditions no less than chronological order. Fourth, the traditional view toward Buddhist teachings still has its value, insofar as the logic of belief provides a rational basis for this view. Fifth, Quan (權) and Shi (實) form better evaluative standards and criteria than correctness and objectivity. Finally, this study argues that it is better to hold a pluralistic and open attitude for interpreting Buddhist history. In this way, the five-stage distinction, while a “historical distortion” for an objective scholar, is actually “religious correctness” for the Buddhist practitioner. Even if it is an error, it is a “beautiful error.”
|
|
|
20.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2020 >
Issue: 59
林修德
Hsiu-Te Lin
On Disagreements within Chinese Philosophy
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
本文的核心論題是中國哲學研究方法,本文企圖指出研究關懷的重要性,強調研究關懷的根本分歧將導致研究立場及其進路的不同,並進而衍生出歧異且難以交流的學術意見。研究關懷是更深層的研究動機,研究者能嘗試在彼此相異的研究關懷中找到某些共通點,從而藉此建構出公共性的研究關懷網絡及其分工整合機制。本文嘗試以「求真」做為公共的研究關懷,倡議中國哲學研究關懷得以從傳統「澄清文本意涵『是』什麼?」的模式中,進一步連結「做為普遍真理的中國哲學該『如何』在當代具體實踐?」 的探究。
The main topic of the paper concerns “research methodologies in Chinese philosophy.” It looks like we are talking about more than one methodology. In this paper, I point out that the researcher’s concern plays an important role in academic judgment. Different researchers’ concerns lead to different stances and methods. And different stances and methods in turn lead to different conclusions. What I coin as “the researcher’s concern” might be provisionally understood as a sort of meta-motivation (something that motivates motives). I suggest that among these different concerns we may seek something common. This something common could then be the basis for a public network, which functions as an integrative mechanism encompassing and addressing those different concerns. This paper argues that “seeking truth” should be the common concern of research. It further argues that with this as the basis, the traditional mode of research, being concerned with the meaning of the text, should be integrated with the present concern with how to practice Chinese philosophy after modernity.
|
|
|