|
1.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
45 >
Issue: 1
Rachel Bryant
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Tragic moral conflicts are situations from within which whatever one does—including abstaining from action—will be seriously wrong; even the overall right decision involves violating a moral responsibility. This article offers an account of recovery predicaments, a particular kind of tragic conflict that characterizes the current extinction crisis. Recovery predicaments occur when the human-caused extinction of a species or population cannot be prevented without breaching moral responsibilities to animals by doing violence to or otherwise severely dominating them. Recognizing the harm of acting from within recovery conflicts adds force to appeals for interrogating and dismantling the systems of thinking, valuing, and acting that bring species to the brink of extinction.
|
|
|
2.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
45 >
Issue: 1
Hewei Sophia Duan
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Scientific cognitivism, a main position in Western environmental aesthetics, claims scientific knowledge plays a major role in the aesthetic appreciation of nature. However, the claim is controversial. This study reexamines the history of United States environmental attitudes around the nineteenth century and claims art has played the main role in nature appreciation, even with the emphasis on scientific knowledge. This paper proposes a tri-stage, Scientific Knowledge-Aesthetic Value Transformation Model and argues nature appreciation is indirectly related to knowledge. Scientific knowledge plays a part in the first, pre-appreciation stage and helps build the impression of nature that bridges scientific cognition with aesthetic appreciation in the second, impression-rebuilt stage. Finally, the engagement model is required in the third, appreciation stage. This paper also presents a two-dimensional evaluation criterion to assess various approaches of nature appreciation and artworks.
|
|
|
3.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
45 >
Issue: 1
Gonzalo Salazar,
Valentina Acuña,
Luca Valera
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
The hegemonic discourse of sustainable development adopted as an international alternative solution to the socio-ecological crisis has implied a progression of the modern utopian project and most importantly, an intrinsic contradiction and omission that positions sustainable development as something that is not in any place. To understand, discuss, and transcend this oxymoron, we first review the modern utopian project and analyze its paradigmatic and ontological assumptions about knowledge, time, and space. Second, we show that sustainable development just re-adapted the founding premises of the modern utopias. Third, to transcend the modern utopian facet of sustainable development, we suggest an understanding of sustainability that stems from a topographical way of thinking. We suggest this approach allows us to seek alternatives to the modern epistemology and ontology that have shaped the current dominant vision of sustainable development. Finally, we propose to move from the modern utopia of sustainable development to the praxis of topographical sustainabilities to trigger a more comprehensive and relational praxis of sustainability.
|
|
|
4.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
45 >
Issue: 1
Andrew Frederick Smith
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Centering Indigenous philosophical considerations, ecologies are best understood as kinship arrangements among humans, other-than-human beings, and spiritual and abiotic entities who together through the land share a sphere of responsibility based on both care and what Daniel Wildcat calls “multigenerational spatial knowledge.” Ecologically speaking, all kin can become persons by participating in processes of socialization whereby one engages in practices and performances that support responsible relations both within and across ecologies. Spheres of responsibility are not operable strictly within human relationships, nor do what count as responsibilities necessarily center on the human. No being is born a person or automatically earns this status. Personhood must be gained and can be lost. Indeed, under current ecological conditions across the planet, we arguably inhabit a world full of marginal cases.
|
|
|
|
5.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
45 >
Issue: 1
Pierre André
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
6.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
45 >
Issue: 1
Pierre André
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
7.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
45 >
Issue: 1
Manuel Rodeiro
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
8.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
44 >
Issue: 4
Stijn Bruers
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Is animal farming permissible when animals would have a positive welfare? The happy animal farming problem represent the paradigmatic problem in population ethics, because its simple structure introduces the most important complications of population ethics. Three new population ethical theories that avoid the counter-intuitive repugnant and sadistic conclusions are discussed and applied to the animal farming problem. Breeding farm animals would not be permissible according to these theories, except under some rather unrealistic conditions, such as those farm animals being so happy that they themselves would prefer a continuation of animal farming. Given the fact that many people believe that most farm animals are not so happy and the fact that one can formulate reasonable population ethical theories that condemn happy animal farming, it can be concluded that it is better to avoid animal farming and the consumption of animal products in general.
|
|
|
9.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
44 >
Issue: 4
Dan Hooley
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
This article considers the collective obligations humans have to wild animals. One proposal, put forward by Sue Donaldson and Will Kymlicka, argues that we should understand wild animals as living in sovereign communities, is argued against. A Sovereignty Model is a poor fit for the unique interests of wild animals and requires stretching this concept beyond recognition. Most crucially, however, it ignores and obscures ways that human states must work to prevent their own citizens from harming wild animals. Instead, it is argued that wild animals should be seen as living in Wild Animal Protectorates, a new political category, inspired by protected states that exist among human states. This framework for thinking about the relationship between human states and wild animals has advantages over a Sovereignty Model when it comes to issues of borders, political representation, and international protection.
|
|
|
10.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
44 >
Issue: 4
Sigurd Hverven
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
This article examines the concepts of alienation and identification in the context of the Anthropocene. It is a common claim in environmental thinking that alienation from nature drives ecological destruction and that a part of the cure for such an unhealthy relationship to nature is to recover a sense of identification with nature. The article challenges this view, by arguing that in the Anthropocene identification with nature may not be solely good, alienation from nature may not be solely bad, and identification and alienation may not be mutually exclusive phenomena. This thesis is defended through a critique of Arne Næss’s view on identification and alienation, and by drawing and elaborating on Simon Hailwood’s study of alienation in environmental philosophy and Adorno’s critique of “identity-thinking.” It also considers a specific case, the so-called “Plastic Whale” that was stranded outside the coast of Norway in 2017.
|
|
|
11.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
44 >
Issue: 4
Simo Kyllönen
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Current ecological threats, such as the sixth mass extinction or climate change, highlight the need to evaluate the moral implications of changing populations, both human and non-human. The paper sketches a non-anthropocentric and multispecies sufficientarian account of population ethics. After discussing several other options for multispecies population ethics, the paper proposes a two-level account of multispecies sufficientarianism, according to which the value of populations depend on two kinds of sufficientarian thresholds. First, there is a species-relativized individual-level threshold for what species-specific flourishing is for an organism. Second, there is a population-level threshold for a sufficiently viable population enough to support the species-specific flourishing of the current and future members of that population. The paper concludes by discussing some of the practical implications and concerns raised by the two-level account suggested.
|
|
|
|
12.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
44 >
Issue: 4
Tyler Cooper-Kolb,
Allen A. Thompson
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
13.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
44 >
Issue: 4
Julia D. Gibson
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
14.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
44 >
Issue: 4
Ronald Sandler
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
15.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
44 >
Issue: 4
Valerie Soon
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
16.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
44 >
Issue: 4
Steven Vogel
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
17.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
44 >
Issue: 4
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
18.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
44 >
Issue: 4
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
19.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
44 >
Issue: 3
Allen Thompson
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
20.
|
Environmental Ethics:
Volume >
44 >
Issue: 3
Marion Hourdequin,
Allen Thompson
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|