|
61.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2015 >
Issue: 49
王志輝
Zhi-Hue Wang
Aristotle’s Criticism of the Platonic Division of the Soul
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
亞理斯多德在《論靈魂》第三書第九章,對柏拉圖的靈魂劃分作出相當 嚴厲的批判。他指出,無論是柏拉圖的靈魂三分(「理性」、「意氣」、「慾 望」),還是柏拉圖主義者所抱持,一般流行的靈魂二分(擁有理性」與「缺 乏理性」兩部分),都有相當大的問題。因為,首先,按照柏拉圖的靈魂劃 分方式,靈魂可以是無限被劃分的。其次,柏拉圖的靈魂劃分,完全忽略了 「吸收養分」的能力,其實是一種獨立的靈魂能力,而不能與其它靈魂部分 或能力混為一談。再者,按照靈魂二分的方式,知覺該歸類為「擁有理性」還是「缺乏理性」的部分,也不清楚。最後,亞理斯多德認為,柏拉圖靈魂 劃分的最不合理之處,在於將原本單一的「欲求能力」分割開,以致於在理 性部分中出現了「希求」,在「缺乏理性」部分中又出現了「慾望」與「意 氣」等,以致於在靈魂三部份中,每一部份都會有欲求。本文打算依次檢視這些批判。此外,本文打算提出的一個觀點是,亞理 斯多德對柏拉圖靈魂劃分之批判,符合他一般對柏拉圖哲學的批判方式:J. Annas 與G. Fine 皆指出,亞理斯多德在批評柏拉圖理型論時,通常會相當 嚴格地堅持柏拉圖文本上的文字意義,但不肯從柏拉圖的角度與哲學立場, 寬大、善意地解讀這些文字;反之,亞理斯多德經常會根據自己的一些預設 與哲學見解,嚴格地檢驗柏拉圖文本中的字句,有時他甚至會將柏拉圖的說 法脫離原有的脈絡來解讀。當然,亞理斯多德這麼作的理由,並非是為了刻 意刁難柏拉圖,而是為了從柏拉圖哲學中得出某些重要的哲學意涵,並藉此 顯示自身哲學立場的合理性。本文將顯示,亞理斯多德對柏拉圖靈魂劃分的 批判,充分展現了這種批判方式的特點。
In De Anima III 9, Aristotle raises a series of criticisms against the Platonic division of the soul. He firstly indicates that the parts of the soul seem to be infinite, and not confined to the calculative, spirited, and the appetitive part, as Plato describes. Secondly, Plato’s tripartition of the soul almost neglects the nutritive part as an independent capacity of the soul. Moreover, although the Platonists simplifies Plato’s tripartition and transformed it into a bipartition, it is not easy to assign the perceptive part either to therational or the irrational part. Finally, Aristotle thinks that it is totally unreasonable for the Platonic soul-division to split the desiderative part up, which should be one and single capacity of the soul; for then there would be wish in the calculative, appetite and spirit in the irrational part, such that in each part of the soul there would be desire.In this article I shall explain these criticisms respectively. However, I will not treat them as though they were isolated, but will show that they belong to Aristotle’s overall criticism against Platonism. J. Annas and G. Fine have suggested that in criticizing Plato’s theory of forms, Aristotle usually finds fault with this theory in an uncharitable and even arrow way. Sometimes he takes an inexact and vague Platonic claim, and provides one literal and natural reading of it on which he then proceeds to attack. Sometimes he reads a Platonic claim not in a way Plato would accept, but in a way which derives from the assumptions of his own metaphysics or from his own understandings about Platonism. Sometimes he criticizes a Platonic argument even in isolation from the original context in Plato’s dialogues. In so doing, however, Aristotle does not intend to misinterpret Plato; his aim is not to record Plato’s arguments straightforwardly, but rather to reconstruct them in a way that will provide philosophical illumination, so that we can learnsomething important about Platonism and the plausibility of Aristotle’s alternative. This article will show that in principle, Aristotle’s criticisms of the Platonic soul-division are compatible with his general mode of criticism against Platonism.
|
|
|
62.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2015 >
Issue: 49
Hua-kuei Ho
何畫瑰
理性的慾望:柏拉圖對慾望的看法 與《饗宴》裡厄律克希馬可斯「愛的醫療」
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Confronted with the stereotype of a rationalistic Plato, the paper argues for the value of desire at its own right in Plato. To explore the relation between desire and rationality in Plato, I choose Eryximachus’ medicine in the Symposium as an object of comparison. Eryximachus’ τέχνη, representing the Hippocratic medical knowledge, is in conformity with Plato’s earlier requirement of knowledge, that is, giving a rational account. The medicine achieves the harmony by balancing the good and bad desires. Plato’s philosophy, however, goes beyond the epistemic model of rational science or τέχνη. On the treatment of desire, he does not follow the discrimination of good and bad desires in medicine, nor does he even out the different desire, because as the doctor. Plato’s philosophy needs the strength of desire, because—though desire sometimes becomes irrational—it is the vital strength of the soul to pursue philosophy.
面對一般對柏拉圖「理性主義」的刻板印象,這篇論文試圖論述:對柏 拉圖而言,「慾望」本身具有價值。為進一步探討柏拉圖哲學中慾望和理性 的關係,文中將以《饗宴》裡厄律克希馬可斯的醫學談話,作為比較的對象。 厄律克希馬可斯的「技藝」(τέχνη),即,希波克拉底派的醫學,符合柏拉 圖早期對知識的要求,也就是:知識必須要能提出合理的說明;此外,當時 的醫學是在藉由好慾望與壞慾望之間的平衡,而使人內在各成分達致健康與 和諧。然而,這裡提出的解釋是:柏拉圖的哲學超出了理性科學或技藝的知 識範本;在對慾望的處理上,他不依循醫學對慾望好壞的區分,他的和諧概 念也保留了理性與非理性慾望並存的差異。柏拉圖哲學需要慾望的力量,慾望雖然可能變成非理性,卻也是靈魂追求哲學不可缺少的力量。
|
|
|
63.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2015 >
Issue: 49
林明照
Ming-Chao Lin
The Ethical Meaning of “Helping Heaven” in Wang Chuanshan’s Interpretation
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
船山透過詮解《莊子》,提出了許多深刻的哲學問題及理論。其中對《莊 子》「相天」說的詮解,尤其值得關注。原因大致有二:首先,船山認為內 篇最能直接表現莊子的思想,而其精髓正可歸結於《莊子》中的相天之說; 其次,船山在將《莊子》哲學的核心論點歸結為相天說時,又據之作為分判 《莊子》與儒、釋、玄等其他哲學家派理論優劣的標準。本文在於對船山《莊 子解》中「相天」說的倫理意義進行討論,全文的討論主要包括三個部分, 首先將指出在船山的理解下,《莊子》的「相天」說在於回答一根本問題:我們有什麼理由認為生比死更有價值?以及由此引生的另一個問題:為什麼 不是每一種人格品質或行為特質都具同等價值?其次,將從相天說所關涉的 生死形上意義,來說明在船山的詮解中,《莊子》透過相天說對於前述問題 的基本回答。接著,本文將對船山所詮解的相天說的倫理意義作出探討。
Chuanshan presents lots of philosophical questions and theories via his interpretation on Zhuangzi, and the one about the concept of “Helping Heaven” especially deserves our attention. There are at least two reasons for this. First, in Chuanshan’s mind, the Inner Chapters is the representative of Zhuangzi’s thought, and the core in it is the concept, “Helping Heaven”. Second, Chuanshan regards “Helping Heaven” not only as the core theory in Zhuangzi but also as the standard to evaluate different theories in ancient Chinese philosophy.The discussion of this paper is divided into three parts. First, in Chuanshan’s interptretation, Zhuangzi’s “Helping Heaven” tells us why living is more valuable than death. From this viewpoint, we can ask further why not all personalities or behaviors have the same value. In the second part, we according to Chuanshan’s interpretation, figure out the answer to the question above from the metaphysical meaning of Zhuangzi’s “Helping Heaven”. In the end, the paper discusses the ethical meaning of “Helping Heaven” in Chuanshan’s interpretation.
|
|
|
64.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2015 >
Issue: 49
張忠宏
Chung-Hung Chang
On Zhu Xi’s Criticisms of Cheng Yi’s Understanding of the Book of Changes
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
朱熹對程頤的批評表面上看起來駁雜而不一致,但深入分析他的論點,可以看出他的批評有一致而深刻的重要性。簡言之,朱熹認為《程氏易傳》 脫離了《易》之筮法與象數,不能說明做人做事的道理、天地自然之數、宇 宙及存有架構等天地之理,如何透過筮法及《易》的表象系統整合在六十四 卦的變化裏。《程氏易傳》之所以有這個問題,是因為程頤缺乏整合義理、 象數與筮法的問題意識,並且輕忽邵雍的先天易學的重要性。對朱熹來說, 唯有邵雍的先天易學可以統合象數、義理與筮法;程頤不能、也不應拒絕先 天易學。
Zhu Xi’s criticisms of Cheng-Shi-Yi-Zhuan seem to be diverse and inconsistent. Further analyses, however, show the contrary. To put it very briefly, Zhu Xi’s complaints were mainly due to Cheng Yi’s failure to bring about a coherent theory that can integrate xiang-shu, yi-li, and shi-fa, as well as his lack of awareness of the significance of such an integration. The reason why Cheng Yi failed in both regards was in turn due to his ignorance of the theoretical roles Shao Yong’s xian-tien-yi-xue can play. By demonstratingwhat those theoretical roles are and why they are so important to Zhu Xi, this paper explicates Zhu Xi’s own understanding of the Book of Changes.
|
|
|
65.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2014 >
Issue: 48
丁福寧
Paschal Fu-Ning Ting
The Metaphysical Foundation of Aquinas’ Anthropology
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
人的完整統一性及靈魂不朽是中世紀時期人學最為困擾,也是爭議最多的 兩個問題。哲學家以二元論及普遍形質論來解釋人的完整性。如此二元論的人學思想以不同的方式成為中世紀時期主流的人學思想。多瑪斯反對任何形式的 二元論,他為人學尋找形上的統一基礎。為多瑪斯,人的完整統一性要求實體形式的統一性,靈魂是人的實體形式 及在自身的實體。唯人的靈魂是受造的,它的存有是分享自存有本身(Ipsum esse)。理性靈魂的本性是精神的,它是人的本質,唯非人的完整的種(species)。 精神的靈魂被賦予存有,它是自立的實體,但不在自身分開地存在,理性的精 神靈魂以其存有統一人的靈魂與身體,如此人具有完整的統一性。存有為現 實,是統一性的基礎,它具絕對的優先性。多瑪斯的存有為現實的概念超越亞 理斯多德形式為現實的概念,如此他為精神的理性奠定形上基礎。故在人的本 體結構上有雙重的潛能與現實的組合;在形上層次是存有-現實與本質-潛能 的組合。在物理層次是靈魂-形式(現實)與身體-質料(潛能)的組合。但 理性靈魂因是自立的實體,它是內在地獨立於身體。理性靈魂因其有存有,具 不朽的形上條件。
During the Middle Ages, the two problems which philosophers concern the most are the holistic unity of man and the immortality of soul. In order to explain these basic Christian beliefs, philosophers adopt the dualism and universal hylomorphism. The reason to take such a stance is to ensure the immortality of soul.For Aquinas, the human rational soul is both the substantial form of body and the substance in its own right, and the holistic unity of man requires the unity of the substantial form. Since the rational soul is created by God, its esse (being) participates in Ipsum Esse. Rational soul is the essence of humans, but not its complete species. It needs to be united with a body. It is spiritual by nature. Once the rational soul is created, it has being, it is a subsistent substance, but not exists separately by itself. The being of therational soul then unites the composit man’s soul and body. Being is the unifying principle. It has absolute priority. There are double composition of potency and act in man’s ontological structure. On metaphysical level, the composition of being-act (or actus essendi) and essence-potency. On physical level, the soul (act-form) and body (potency-matter), yet the rational soul is essentially independent from body. The being of the rational soul is its metaphysical foundation of immortality.
|
|
|
66.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2014 >
Issue: 48
鄧克 銘
Keh-Ming Deng
An Analysis of Fang Yizhi’s View on Zhuangzi’s Xiaoyaoyou
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
莊子在〈逍遙遊〉以寓言的方式表達高遠的精神世界,其意境及途徑引起 後人不斷地探索。方以智收集大量的古今註解,會通儒釋道三家思想,以獨特 的寫作方法詮解該篇蘊藏的豐富內容。本文從三個層面說明方以智詮釋的重要觀念。第一:關於莊子「小大之辨」 的問題,方以智強調小與大之無差別性與相異性,以消除片面的執著。第二: 方以智從「有」與「無」之對立的觀念,說明兩者相互否定、相互成立的關係; 並主張「不落有無」又「不離有無」,才能在現實生活中得到自在。第三:方 以智會通儒釋道,說明逍遙遊之途徑與形態,正是其自身生活經歷的反映。經 由本文的分析,可以了解方以智主張去除偏執以得心靈自由的詮釋方法與理論 依據。
In his writing, “Xiaoyaoyou” (逍遙遊), Zhuangzi uses parables to express his profound and innermost spiritual world. His artistic conception and approach inspire ongoing research by subsequent generations. Fang Yizhi analyzes numerous ancient and modern interpretations of Zhuangzi’s piece, applies Confucian, Buddhist, and Taoist thinking, and uses his unique writing method to interpret the rich content in Zhuangzi’s writing.In the present article, important concepts of Fang Yizhi’s interpretation are analyzed from three different angles. First, regarding Zhuangzi’s argument of “the distinction between micro and macro” (小大之辨), Fang Yizhi intends to eliminate this persistent polarized view by emphasizing that micro and macro are indistinguishable. Second, Fang Yizhi uses the conflict between the concepts of “existence” (有) and “nonexistence” (無) to illustrate the relationship between mutual negation and mutual confirmation. He also advocates that if we “are not biased by or do not insist on either existence or nonexistence” and “do not break away from the confronting phenomena of existence andnonexistence”, then we shall be at ease in our real life. Third, Fang Yizhi applies Confucianism, Buddhism, and Taoism to illustrate the approach and structure of Xiaoyaoyou. This is precisely the reflection of his own life experiences. Through the analysis of the present article, one can understand the interpretation methods and theoretical basis Fang Yizhi advocates to remove any polarized view in order to obtain freedom of the soul.
|
|
|
67.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2014 >
Issue: 48
張忠 宏
Chung-Hung Chang
Dao, Technê and Cultivating Life: Following Cook Ding’s Lead
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
本文主張,莊子的「養生」是涵養生命之意,因此它的養生觀包含養親 的要求。「庖丁解牛」不是寓言,而是莊子舉例說明技藝在生命之涵養中扮 演了什麼樣的角色。技藝的重要性,不在於它能帶來心流經驗,而在於它能 將世界揭露為豐富多元、且可悠遊徜徉的場域。欲得養生,就必須擁有良好 的技藝,包括與父母相處、將父母揭露為相互成全、攜手共遊的養親技藝。 基於這樣一種養生觀,莊子雖然高度重視人倫的要求,認為得道者必能養 親,卻並未進一步進行倫理學與政治哲學思考。
According to Zhuangzi, the meaning of Yang-Sheng is all about life-cultivation. This can be seen from the fact that it is one of Yang-Sheng’s requirements to keep good company with one’s parents. The story of Cook Ding, as presented in the book by Zhuangzi, is meant to provide an insight into the importance of technê in life. To put it briefly, technê is important not because it can bring about flow experience, but because it can reveal the world as one in which one can wander about and be playful with valuable things in multiple dimensions. Thus, it is a necessary condition for anyone who wants to cultivate the meaning of life to be able to master at least some skills, especially the ones involved in keeping good company with one’s parents. As a consequence, Zhuangzi is quite successful at giving a daoist twist to filial obedience, though he confineshimself not to pursue further ethical and/or political theorizations.
|
|
|
68.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2014 >
Issue: 48
Hsiu-Lin Ku
古秀 鈴
語意理論與可及原則
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
This paper aims to defend François Recanati’s Availability Principle approach to semantics by illuminating and responding to two major challenges from minimalists, in particular from Emma Borg: the first concerns the notion of intuitive content and “awareness-of” presupposed in the Availability Principle, and the second concerns whether the principle makes a semantic theory unfit with normativity and compositionality. I lead the discussion toward the kernel question--the bearer of the semantic content--and show that the Availability Principle is appropriate if we respect the empirical basis of meaning.
本文試圖替François Recanati 回應以Emma Borg 為主的兩面向批評,而 得以闡明並辯護其所主張的可及原則:其一面向是關於可及原則所預設的 「直覺內容」與「意識到」兩概念,其二面向是關於是否滿足可及原則會使 的語意理論無法滿足語言的規範性與組構性。我將引導此爭論至問題核心 ─即語意內容的承載者─重新審視何以一般咸認為語句本身有其客觀、不受脈絡影響而改變的語意內容,並論證若我們顧及意義的經驗基礎,則可及原則是恰當的。
|
|
|
69.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2014 >
Issue: 48
Tzu-Wei Hung
洪子 偉
心智模組的酵素模型及其困難
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
The enzyme model (EM), inspired by biological enzyme catalysis, is a computational-functional description of information processing and distribution in modular cognitive systems. It has been argued that EM offers advantages in solving both the allocation problem and global computation and thus may play a role in upholding the massive modularity hypothesis (MMH). This paper, however, argues that EM solutions are untenable, as EM avoids the infinite regress of allocation problem only at a high cost and with several critical drawbacks. Moreover, to clarify global processes, EM needs to satisfy two necessary conditions: first to demonstrate that the EM allows cross module communication, and second to be sensitive to not only the syntax but also the semantics of representations. I argue that EM only satisfies the first condition and thus fails to hold.
「酵素模型」指的是借用生物學中酵素催化機制的概念,來說明認知科 學中「大量模組假說」在計算與功能層次上有關資訊處理與分配之模型。酵 素模型的最大優點在於回應了「訊號配置」與「整體計算」兩難題,從而替 大量模組假說提供有利的辯護基礎。但本文之目的,在論證酵素模型的這兩 個回應並不成立。一方面,酵素模型在避免訊號配置的無限後退時會產生新 的困難。另一方面,要說明整體計算至少得滿足兩個必要條件:一是跨模組 的訊號交換是可能的、二在於模組能夠不只是針對輸入訊號的語法結構來處 理訊號。本文將論證酵素模型頂多說明如何滿足第一個必要條件,而沒有釐 清第二個必要條件如何在該模型中實現。換言之,酵素模型對兩難題的回應 不成立。因此,酵素模型無法用以支持大量模組假說。
|
|
|
70.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2014 >
Issue: 47
陳政 揚
Cheng-Yang Chen
A Study of Wang Zhi’s Criticisms of the Deification in the Commentary of the Zhengmeng by an Analysis of the Three Aspectsin the Idea of “Ultimate Voidness (Taixu 太虛)”
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
設若研讀哲學家的代表著作,是吾人探究其思想的必要條件之一,則逐句 解析張載思想論述的明清《正蒙》注,顯然是研究橫渠思想在明清哲學之發展 時,所無可忽視的一環。尤其歷來注解《正蒙》者,不乏高攀龍,王夫之等望 重士林,或在哲學史上具有獨創見解者。然而在當代張載學研究中,相關議題 似乎仍較少引起學者間的討論興趣。基於此,本文以清代《正蒙》學研究為論 述起點,旨在澄清李光地在《注解正蒙》中對張載神化觀的詮釋,以及王植在 《正蒙初義》中如何由釐清「太虛」概念,批判李《注》之非。全文共分為四 項研究環節:首先,由於王植以澄清「太虛」概念為解讀《正蒙》與衡定諸注 之關鍵,本文先扼要說明「太虛」之三層義。其次,本文將指出李《注》對「太 虛」之詮釋,以及王植對李《注》太虛義之批判。再者,由於李《注》不僅嘗 試解消「太虛」之本體義,而且以理氣二分的理論架構,詮釋橫渠虛氣一體之 神化觀。本文將指出李《注》對橫渠神化觀之新詮。最後,本文將藉太虛三層 義,指出《正蒙初義》的洞見以及李《注》神化觀的侷限。
In order to understand the content and significance of Zhan Zai’ thought, commentarial works on the Zhengmeng during the Ming and Qing period areindispensable because these works present detailed explications on every conceptual terms. Compared to those commentarial works on the Zhang Zai’s thought by Gao Panlong and Wang Fuzhi who have been regarded as rather creative thinkers, other commentarial works during the Qing period have not drawn sufficient scholarly attention. Bearing this in mind, this article aims to explore the two topics: Firstly, it analyzes Li Guangdi’s interpretation on Zhang Zai’s idea of “deification” through Li’s Commentary of the Zhengmeng. And secondly, it also traces Wang Zhi’s elucidation of the concept of “Ultimate Voidness” (Taixu) in his commentarial work, the Basic Meanings of the Zhengmeng, as well as Wang’s correction of initial mistakes in aforementioned Li Guangdi’s commentary.The discussion of this article consists of the following four sub-topics: (1) Wang Zhi’s exposition of three aspects in the concept of “Ultimate Voidness”; (2) Li Guangdi’s interpretation of the term “Ultimate Voidness” and Wang Zhi’s repudiation against it; (3) Li’s argument that the ontological significance of the concept of “Ulitmate Voidness” should be dissolved, and that Zhang Zai’s idea of deification of continuity between vital breath and voidness should be understood by the dualistic framework between principle and vital breath; and (4) Highlighting of Wang’s insight and Li’s limitation of his conception of deification by means of our analysis of the three aspects in the concept of “Ultimate Voidness.”
|
|
|
71.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2014 >
Issue: 47
Cheng-Hung Tsai
蔡政 宏
技藝與理解
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
How can we acquire understanding? Linda Zagzebski has long claimed that understanding is acquired through, or arises from, mastering a particular practicaltechnê. In this paper, I explicate Zagzebski’s claim and argue that the claim is problematic. Based on a critical examination of Zagzebski’s claim, I propose, inconclusion and in brief, a new claim regarding the acquisition of understanding.
人是如何獲得「理解」?德性知識論的代表人物Linda Zagzebski 長久 來宣稱「理解的獲得來自於對技藝的掌握」。在本文中,作者闡釋Zagzebski 的宣稱,並指出這宣稱的問題。透過對Zagzebski 之宣稱的批判性檢視,作 者在文後提供另一修改自Zagzebski 的理解獲得觀點。
|
|
|
72.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2014 >
Issue: 47
傅皓 政
Hao-Cheng Fu
Nonmonotonic Reasoning and Defaults: On Rott’s Counterexamples
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
此篇論文旨在以萊特於1980 年所提出的預建邏輯系統,消除洛特對 AGM 理論的單調性原則提出的反例。相較於古典邏輯,雖然AGM 理論主張 知識狀態具備均衡性,並建構基本函映的預設說明信念變遷,但是許多哲學 家認為該理論有某些基本原則值得質疑,洛特即指出AGM 理論主張原有知 識狀態的某個信念弱化之後,並不會影響原知識狀態的單調性並不成立。然 而,洛特的反例之所以成立,在於可能出現相同語句卻具有不同資訊價值的 情況,不過,洛特也並未提出適當的方式說明處理非單調的信念變遷過程。 因此,我在這篇論文中要以AGM 理論結合預建邏輯的方法消除洛特提出的 反例,亦即主張在AGM 理論中加入預建邏輯的推論規則,可以適當地處理 非單調的信念變遷過程。
This paper aims to dissolve Rott’s counterexamples in terms of default logic proposed by Reiter in 1980. In his counterexample, Rott pointed out that some fundamental principles in AGM theory which meet the property of monotonicity are implausible because it seems unable to handle the processes of nonmonotonic reasoning which are common in our ordinary reasoning. In contrast to classical logic, AGM theory indeed developed a prominent way to deal with belief change, whereas many philosophers still casted doubts on the fundamental principles in AGM theory. For example, there might be some sentences in one’s belief set which are of the same form but different in information value and AGM theory does not commit it. Nevertheless, Rott failed to suggest a plausible way to fix the defect of AGM theory, so I aim to propose a suitable way to dissolve the problem of the processes of nonmontonic reasoning in virtue of the association of AGM theory with default logic.
|
|
|
73.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2014 >
Issue: 47
Caleb Liang
梁益 堉
知覺的反個體主義與視覺科學
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
I discuss the nature of visual perception from an interdisciplinary perspective. The target of investigation is Tyler Burge’s theory of perceptual anti-individualism, according to which perceptual states constitutively depend on relations between perceivers and the external world. Burge argues that this theory is presupposed by vision science. My goal is to argue that perceptual anti-individualism is not the only theoretical choice. First, I consider the notion of homeostasis and suggest how it may cast doubt on the perceptual norms in Burge’s theory. Second, I argue that many phenomena studied by vision science can be explained without positing Burge’s notions of veridicality and singular representation. Third, I consider some empirical theories and argue that vision science does not uniquely favor Burge’s theory. I conclude that perceptual anti-individualism is not the only framework for understanding visual perception.
本文從跨領域的角度探討視覺的根本性質,並以Tyler Burge 的「知覺 的反個體主義」(perceptual anti-individualism)為研究對象。根據這一理論,知覺狀態的本質乃是由知覺者與外在環境的互動關係而定。Burge 提出論證 主張:視覺科學(vision science)預設了這個理論。本文反對這個觀點,並 企圖從三方面來論證:「知覺的反個體主義」不是我們理解視覺的唯一理論 選項。首先,我討論「體內恆定」(homeostasis)的概念,並指出這概念會 使我們對Burge 理論中的「知覺規範」(perceptual norms)產生質疑。第二,我以論證指出:許多視覺科學所研究的現象,可以不必預設Burge 理論中的 「正確性」(veridicality)和「單一表徵」(singular representation)也能得到解釋。第三,我討論一些有關視覺的科學理論並論證:許多視覺科學領域中 的看法其實不支持Burge 的理論。本文的結論是:「知覺的反個體主義」並 不是瞭解視覺本質唯一可選的理論架構。
|
|
|
74.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2013 >
Issue: 46
丁 福 寧
Paschal Fu-Ning Ting
Stoics on Oikeiōsis
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
視為己有(oikeiōsis)概念是斯多噶學派倫理學的特色。這一概念在它 的泛神物質一元論的本體基礎建立上,宇宙是由神、人和自然世界共同組成 的一個完整的神聖實體。神聖理性掌握和管理宇宙整體。物質是唯一真實 的。人是由靈魂與身體結構起的有組織的整全個體。視為己有具有發展的歷 程。在第一階段,所有具有靈魂的動物,當依照自然生活,將自己自然狀態 中所有的視為己有,努力地保存自己。這是來自動物的本能。人在出生之始,如同動物依照本能生活,及至成年,理性方發展出來。在第二階段人的依照 自然生活當是依照理性生活。第二階段的視為己有是人當意識和認識到依自身的自然狀態的生活亦即追求至善和渡德行的生活。在第三階段,鑒於所有的人具有相同的理性,同屬於一個人類大家族,oikeiōsis 因而具有社會面 向,人要將他人的善視為己有。人對他者有責任,要愛人如己。本論文旨在論證斯多噶學派的視為己有之所以建立在泛神物質一元 論,因它反對任何形式的二元論,特別是柏拉圖的二元論;非物質世界和物 質世界之間的二元對立,及人的靈魂與身體之間的二元對立,甚至理性與非 理性之間的二元對立。斯多噶學派的視為己有概念不僅從宇宙是一整體,且 從人是有組織的整全個體探討人與自己,與他人,與自然世界的關係。這種 整全的概念正是柏拉圖否認的。
The concept of oikeiōsis is the characteristic of Stoic ethics. The ontological foundation of the oikeiōsis is based on its pantheistic material monism. Thecosmos is constituted by god (gods), humans and natural world as a complete divine substance. The whole cosmos is controlled and directed by the divinelogos. For the stoics, matter is the only true reality. Man is joined by soul and body as a structured wholistic self. The oikeiōsis is in developing processes.Living in accordance with nature and making all those belong to oneself as one’s own is the first stage of oikeiōsis at the moment of the birth of all the animals,including humans. At this stage animals attain their oikeiōsis by their instincts. At the beginning of its birth, a baby lives in agreement with its nature just as theway animals do. When it grows up, as its reason develops, living in accordance with nature turns out to be living in accordance with reason. The second stage ofoikeiōsis is then to attain summum bonum, leading a virtuous life, since man as rational being is capable of recognizing what his constitution is. Because allmen possess the same reason and belong to the same human family, oikeiōsis by nature has social dimension. At the third stage, a man should take intoaccount of his fellow’s well-being as his own oikeiōsis. A man should love the others as he loves himself.This paper tries to argue why the Stoics’ oikeiōsis concept based on its pantheistic material monism. The reason is its objection to any forms of dualism, especially the Platonic dualism; the dualistic opposition between the immaterial and material worlds, that of the psyche and body, and even that of rational and irrational. The Stoics’ oikeiōsis is not only based on its idea of the wholistic cosmos, but also found on that of the structured wholistic self; i.e. the psychophysical whole and the relations between a human being with itself, with the others, and with the natural world. This kind of wholistic ideas of the cosmos and of humans are what Plato denied.
|
|
|
75.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2013 >
Issue: 46
王文 方
Wen-Fang Wang
Concrete Objects Distinction
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
大多數當代哲學家認為,這個世界裡的事物可以被互相排斥而又共同窮 舉地區分成兩個類:一類是具體的事物類,另一類則是抽象的事物類。問題 在於:這兩類事物之間的區別究竟何在?Hoffman 與Rosenkrantz(2003)曾 經論證說,常見的、對於抽象/具體事物的區分方式存在著一些明顯的問 題,而他們主張以一種新穎的、在他們看來沒有問題的方式去作出這兩類事 物之間的區別。本論文旨在以他們批評其它區分時所使用的策略與標準而去 反對他們所提出的區分,並從而論證兩個要點。首先,本文論證說,抽象/ 具體事物之所以不容易(甚至不可能)找到一個可信的區分方式,原因相當 可能在於:我們對該區分所擁有的任何直覺都是許多不等價與/或混含的區 分互相混淆的結果。其次,本文論證說,抽象/具體事物的區分本身其實不 具有任何哲學上的重要性,因而是一個可以不必深究的問題。
Most contemporary philosophers believe that things in the world can be exhaustively and exclusively divided into two categories: abstract objects and concrete ones, and a main “problem” about this division is where exactly the line between these two categories should be drawn? Hoffman and Rosenkrantz (2003) argued that every ordinary distinction between these two categories was subject to some serious problems and counterexamples, and they therefore proposed a novel distinction that they believed to be completely unproblematic. This paper argues against their proposal by appealing to the same strategy and criterion that they set up for other proposals. This paper also argues for two other points. First, it argues that the fundamental reason why it is so hard (even impossible) to find “the right” distinction between abstract and concrete objects is that philosophers’ “intuition” about the distinction is nothing but the result of conflation and confusion of several non-equivalent and/or vague distinctions. Second, it argues that the problem of the distinction between abstract and concrete objects is of no philosophical significance; it is, therefore, a pseudo problem that need not be investigated at all.
|
|
|
76.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2013 >
Issue: 46
鄭喜 恆
Hsi-Heng Cheng
The Community and the Individual: A Comparative Study of Peirce's Early and James's Pragmatic Views of Truth and Reality
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
裴爾士與詹姆士通常被並列為實用主義的共同創建者,但是兩人的實用 主義哲學實有相當的差異。本文從「個人探究」與「社群探究」這兩個層次 的區分入手來比較裴爾士早期與詹姆士的實用主義實在觀與真理觀、以及兩 人對於經驗探究方法的刻畫,並且指出裴爾士認為「真理」、「實在」與「經 驗探究方法」必須在社群探究層次上才能獲得恰當的闡釋,然而詹姆士堅持 從個人探究層次來闡釋這些觀念,這也可以解釋為何詹姆士的實用主義真理 觀曾經遭受到如此多的質疑與誤解。
Peirce and James have been regarded as co-founders of pragmatism, but their pragmatisms differ significantly. This paper examines and compares, onthe basis of the distinction between the levels of community and individual inquiry, Peirce’s early and James’s pragmatic views of truth, reality, and methodof inquiry; and points out that Peirce argues that these three notions could be satisfactorily explicated only on the level of community inquiry, whereas Jamesinsists on characterizing them on the level of individual inquiry─this can explain why James’s pragmatic view of truth has suffered severe objections and misunderstandings.
|
|
|
77.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2013 >
Issue: 46
蔡龍 九
Lung-Chiu Tsai
A Revaluation of Wang Yang Ming’s “Zhi Hsin He Yi”
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
本文欲釐清王陽明論述「知行合一」時的細部可議之處。當代前輩學者 們曾針對此「知行合一」問題提出多種看法,包含留意到「一念發動處」是 否適用於「知行合一」的教法。陳來先生針對此處提出「重行」之說,而李 明輝先生則以「意念屬行」的方式來解消此糾葛……等。針對前輩學者們的 研究成果,筆者欲補充說明有關「知行合一」與「意念」細部關聯,並在陽 明所認同的「知行合一」架構下,重新論說「善念」、「惡念」是否屬「行」 的問題,並針對前述兩位前輩學者的看法做出調和,且回歸陽明論說「知行合一」時的主要涵義。
I will focus upon the arguments of Wang Yang Ming’s theory of “Zhi Hsin He Yi”(知行合一) in this paper. Concerning this issue, scholars have proposed various interpretations, pondering whether “Yi Nian Fa Dong Chu” (一念發動處) is applicable to “Zhi Hsin He Yi.” For instance, Chen Lai accentuates “Chong Hsin” (重行) and argues that “Yi Nian Fa Dong Chu” is not applicable to “Zhi Hang He Yi.” Besides Li Ming Hui suggests that “Yi Nian”(意念) is also an “act” in “Zhi Hsin He Yi” so as to solve the entanglement. Inspired by these researches, I intend to analyze the intricate relationship between “Zhi Hang He Yi” and “Yi Nian.” Furthermore, I will reevaluate whether “Shan Nian”(善念) and “Er Nian”(惡念) can be categorized as an “act” in Wang Yang Ming’s theoretical framework. Finally, I attempt toassimilate the arguments proposed by Chen Lai and Li Ming Hui while returning to the core principle of Wang Yang Ming’s “Zhi Hsin He Yi.”
|
|
|
78.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2013 >
Issue: 46
陳平 坤
Ping-Kun Chen
The Dharma Approach for Pacifying the Mind in the Chan Teachings of Sheng Yen: Is the Chan Practice of “Huatou” Consistent with the Thought of “Non-Abiding”?
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
「看話禪」是中華禪門的著名禪修方法,而「無住」則為《六祖壇經》 的根本思想。本論文參酌聖嚴法師所教授的看話禪法,嘗試探討「看話禪」 與「無住」思想是否融貫一致的問題,藉以針對看話禪法提出若干省思。本論文認為,看話禪法在義理上所預設的,是《楞伽經》中認為妄念可 斷而且應當斷除淨盡的思想,而不是《六祖壇經》中所說妄念不可斷而且不 應該起心動念要將它們斷除淨盡的思想。換言之,真正與看話禪法相融貫 的,是主張「捨念清淨」的如來藏心常住思想,而不是宣說「念念不住」的 般若法空無住思想;亦即是北宗禪思想,而不是南宗禪思想。因此,「看話 禪」作為一種禪修方法,在思想和方法一貫的意義下,更準確地說,乃是屬 於北宗禪修之道,而不是屬於南宗禪修之道。雖然「看話禪」也是解脫成佛 的方便法門之一,但是如果根據慧能在《六祖壇經》中所教禪法來看,則它 並不是貫徹始終能讓人究竟「安心」的修行法門;除非採取聖嚴教授看話禪 法時的類似辦法,亦即借助一些來自《六祖壇經》乃至般若經典的觀念,扣 緊「無住」思想而把它導入能夠發揮究竟安心效果的「念念不住」之禪觀實 踐活動中。
“Kanhua Chan”, normally known as the Chan practice of huatou, is a famous method in the Chinese Chan tradition, while “non-abiding” is a fundamental thought in the Platform Sutra of the Sixth Patriarch. Based on the Chan method of huatou taught by Master Sheng Yen, this thesis tries to investigate whether there is consistence between the Chan practice of huatou and the thought of “non-abiding”, so as to put forward some critical comments on the Chan method of huatou. This thesis points out that the Chan practice of huatou presupposes the thought of Lankavatara Sutra that deluded thoughts can and should be eliminatedcompletely, rather than the thought as expressed by Huineng the Sixth Patriarch in the Platform Sutra that deluded thoughts need not be eliminated and thatone should not give rise to the thought of eliminating them completely. In other words, what is consistent with the Chan practice of huatou is the thoughtof ever-abiding mind of tathagata-garbha that advocates “the complete elimination of deluded thoughts,” rather than the prajna thought of non-abiding that advocates “non-abiding from one thought-moment to another,” so it is a method that follows the Chan principle of Northern School, rather than that of Southern School.Precisely speaking, therefore, the Chan method of huatou is, judged by the characteristics of its method, a Chan approach pertaining to the Northern School, not the Southern School. Although it is also one of the expedient Dharma methods for achieving liberation and buddhahood, it is, from the perspective of Huineng’s Chan teaching, not a method of practice that can truly help people pacify their mind ultimately, unless one adopts the manner Master Sheng Yen used in teaching the Chan practice of huatou, a manner that, based on some concepts derived from the prajna sutras and the Platform Sutra, strictly adheres to the thought of “non-abiding,” guiding it to the method of Chan practice that can ultimately bring about the effect of pacifying the mind.
|
|
|
79.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2013 >
Issue: 45
孫雲 平
Yun-Ping Sun
History and Life: Nietzsche’s Criticism of Historical Methodology and Teleology in Unfashionable Observations
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
本文嘗試釐清尼采於〈歷史對人生之利弊〉一文中對於歷史的觀點以及 其對歷史跟人生關係的主張。其中主要說明尼采於本篇論文如何批判「歷史」 目的論及歷史書寫的方法論:尼采認為人類活動以及歷史本身沒有終極目 的、歷史書寫不可能達至客觀的要求。換言之,追求客觀性目標的歷史書寫 將因為作為純粹的理論性知識而成為人類生活與行動的阻礙、使人類的生命 萎縮與僵化。歷史知識以及記憶在尼采的眼中,成為人類生命之自主性創造 與實踐的絆腳石。藉此尼采展示人類個體的生命特徵:生命不僅不可能永恆 不朽、甚至並非實體性的存在、同時不必然是合乎理性、道德的與正義的。生命是必朽的、是一個不斷流變的、及難以理性掌握的現象。通過對歷史與歷史書寫態度的分析,尼采強調生命必須不斷地透過自主的抉擇、行動與實 踐來自我實現與自我超越。
This paper tries to elucidate what Nietzsche’s view of history and his thesis about the relationship between history and life would be in his essay On the Advantages and Disadvantages of History for the Life. It is above all to explain how Nietzsche criticizes the teleology of history and the methodology of historiography in this article: Nietzsche claims that there would be no ultimate destination of human activities and the history itself, and that historical writing could not fulfill the objective standard. In another words, the historical writing which runs after the goal of objectivity would, as purely theoretical knowledge, become an obstacle of human life and action, and would then wither and ossify the human life. Historical knowledge and memory would be, in the sight of Nietzsche, a stone of stumbling to autonomous creativity and practice of human life. By this Nietzsche demonstrates the characteristics of human individual life: Neither can life be eternal and immortal, nor would it even be a substantial being; at the same time, it would not necessarily be rational, moral and just. Life is mortal and is a perpetually changing and unfathomable phenomenon. By analyzing the attitude toward history and historical writing, Nietzsche lays the emphasis that life would have to realize itself and surpass itself by the autonomous determination, action and practice.
|
|
|
80.
|
NTU Philosophical Review:
Year >
2013 >
Issue: 45
沈享 民
Hsiang-Min Shen
Zhu Xi’s Critique of the Hu Xiang Scholars’ Understanding of “Humaneness”: An Analysis of How Zhu Xi’s View Differs from Hsieh Liang-Tso’s as Contrasted with Cheng Hao’s Interpretation
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
本文研究朱熹與湖湘學者的兩個辯論:「觀過知仁」與「知覺為仁」,並 論證朱熹對謝良佐與湖湘諸學者的義理之理解並非無據。首先,本文檢視由 朱熹書信與相關文獻所保存下來的論辯內容,並討論朱熹之所以反對湖湘學 者以「知覺」定義「仁」的理據。朱熹認為仁不是一種高妙玄虛的知覺,仁 雖不是知覺本身,但有仁德的人必有知覺。依朱熹,仁專指心之德,即心靈 的卓越品質;有仁德的人以義理為知覺內容,而非只是知覺;知覺本身屬於 智而不是仁。進一步,本文論證:湖湘學者之所以認定知覺為仁,其理由在 於繼受了謝良佐所表述「仁」的內涵,後者遺落了程顥彰顯仁的生動明澈所 善用的類比或譬喻;相對地,謝良佐的表述幾乎接近以定義的方式呈現。是以,即便是朱熹錯解了湖湘學者的義理,在表述方式上,其實事出有因。
This paper focuses on two famous debates concerning “humaneness” between Zhu Xi and the Hu Xiang scholars. Based on the survey of literature, this paper tries to justify, at least partly, what Zhu Xi comprehends about the philosophical position of Hu Xiang School. According to Zhu Xi’s philosophy, “humaneness” specifically labels the complete virtue of mind which exemplifies excellent qualities. On the one hand, Zhu Xi objects to the claim of those Hu Xiang scholars that“humaneness” can be defined as “vivid perception”; on the other hand, he argued that perception is by nature attributed to the intellectual virtue, although the humane person certainly possesses the competence of perception. As a matter of fact, the key point of the two debates between Zhu Xi and the Hu Xiang scholars is how to treat Hsieh Liang-Tso’s interpretation of humaneness.Furthermore, this paper argues that Cheng Hao, Hsieh’s teacher, illustrated distinctively the concept of humaneness in his own analogical or metaphorical way, but Hsieh’s formulation of it is akin to definition of a certain kind. This missed link or the rhetorical nuance is the reason why the Hu Xiang scholars follow Hsieh’s approach to humaneness and Zhu Xi has to argue against their ideas of humaneness.
|
|
|