Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 181-200 of 847 documents


181. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3/4
Robin Attfield

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Cultural transmission in non-literate societies (including that of Homer) is first discussed, partly to test some theories of Dan Sperber, and partly to consider thetheory of memes, which is sometimes held applicable to Homeric formulae, and is considered next. After discussing Sperber's criticism of memeticism, I turn toSperber's susceptibility theory of culture, and his discussions of religion and of music. Further examples drawn from Homeric religion are found to be in tension with aspects of this theory. Two diverse interpretations of susceptibility present in Sperber's text are elicited and contrasted, of which one is criticised and the other welcomed as consistent with the role of reflection, artifice and rationality in the development of culture, activities that theories of culture cannot afford to disregard.

182. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3/4
Robert Theis

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

183. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3/4
Alexiadou Anastasia-Sofia

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

184. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3/4
Fotini Vaki

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

185. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3/4
Drakoulis Nikolinakos

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

critique

186. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3/4
Anastasia Marinopoulou

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

book reviews

187. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3/4
Ellen Fridland

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

188. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 34 > Issue: 1/2
Theodore Scaltsas

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

189. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 34 > Issue: 1/2
Anna Marmodoro

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In his theory of perception Aristotle is committed to the principle that there is a one-to-one correspondence between a sensible quality, the modification of a sense organ by that quality, and the content of the perceptual experience of it. But on the basis of this principle, simultaneous perceptions of different sensible qualities give rise only to distinct perceptual contents. This generates the problem of how we become aware of complex perceptual content, e.g. in discerning red from cold. This paper examines the alternative (although not equally explanatorily powerful) models that Aristotle offers in the De Anima and in his biological works to account for complex perceptual content.

190. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 34 > Issue: 1/2
Nickolas Pappas

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

191. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 34 > Issue: 1/2
Dionysios A. Anapolitanos

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

192. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 34 > Issue: 1/2
Panos Eliopoulos

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Even though Heimarmene is the natural order of things, as it is claimed in the Laws; and although the human being has to participate in that order, as it is written in Timaeus; Plato, at times, tends to be willing to rupture that circle of necessity, that the "naturality" of Heimarmene enforces on man, by finding a potential escape. The human soul is the unambiguous vehicle of this effort. In the writings of the Stoic Seneca, the transcendence of Fate is a matter correlated with the human life and with moral responsibility. His philosophical aim is focused on overcoming the existential conditions which render man a subjugated as well as a non eudaimonistic being. In both philosophers we diagnose a common theoretical orientation: to break through the limitations that Fate imposes on man's freedom in the material world. Certainly there is a difference in the degree, frequency and depth that this is critically established in their thought. In our paper, we mean to: a) ascertain this, b) examine the role of the soul, and c) to recognize the ground where "Paideia" may initiate the transcendence of Fate by human means solely.

critique

193. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 34 > Issue: 1/2
Nickolas Pappas

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

book reviews

194. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 34 > Issue: 1/2
Anastasia Marinopoulou

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
195. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 34 > Issue: 1/2
Brian Seitz

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
196. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 34 > Issue: 1/2
Nickolas Pappas

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

197. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 32 > Issue: 3/4
Pablo García Castillo

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper's aim is to study the Greek simile of the ship of state, since it was born in the Lyric Poetry until its definitive drawing by Plato's hands. It describes the image of Paros' ship, by Archilochus, or the ship of city by Alcaeus and by Theognis. Analyzes how this image improves through the tragedies of Aeschylus and Sophocles, and their moral comprehension of it. And, at last, explains the excellence achieved as the central image on Plato's politic project.

198. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 32 > Issue: 3/4
Robert William Mosimann

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

199. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 32 > Issue: 3/4
Theodoros Christidis, Demetrius Athanassakis

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Our purpose in this paper is to bring about a new meaning of the term λόγοϛ used in the fragments of Heraclitus' work. In ancient Greek literature this term hasmany different meanings. We are going to restrict our interest in those meanings that Heraclitus used in his fragments, where the term λόγοϛ appears ten times.

200. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 32 > Issue: 3/4
D.Z. Andriopoulos

view |  rights & permissions | cited by