Cover of Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science
>> Go to Current Issue

Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science

Teoría, historia y fundamentos de las cientias formales; Teoría, historia y fundamentos de las cientias naturales, humanas y sociales

Volume 7
Toma A and Toma B

Table of Contents

Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 41-60 of 102 documents


seccion vi. fundamentos, filosofia e historia de la fisica

41. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
José Manuel Sánchez Ron

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
42. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Sergio Martínez

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper explores some of the philosophical difficulties involved in the task of clarifying the idea of an irreducible statistical law, by means of an analysis of the paradigmatic example of such a law in the Quantum theory.These are two alternative strategies that can be pursued in clarifying this question. One is to understand this irreductibility by means of one or another interpretation of the Quantum theory. But, as will be shown, the different interpretations of Quantum mechanics lead to radically different and fundamentally incompatible answers to the problem. The second strategy is to try to caracterize this irreducibility “directly”, via a proof of the impossibility of a hidden-variable extension of the statistical formalism of the theory. This strategy culminates with Bell’s theorem which indeed establishes the impossibility of constructing “Iocal” theories of hidden variables. This impossibility result, however, fails to provide us with a satisfying interpretation of the quantum irreductibility, rather, it merely shows how far we are from a solution to the problem.

seccion vii. fundamentos, filosofia e historia de la biologia y de la antropologia

43. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Faustino Cordón

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
44. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Carlos Gurméndez

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
45. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Carlos París

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
46. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Vicente Sanfélix Vidarte

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
47. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Alicia Sánchez-Mazas

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Genetic studies of present human populations are very useful to understand the history of modern Human migrations throughout the world, especially when the results are compared with the information provided by historical linguistics and archaelogy. However, an inaccurate methodology is commonly applied to the analysis of the most recent molecular data and may lead to some erroneous conclusions on our first origins.

seccion viii. la filosofia del lenguaje y su historia

48. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Mauricio Beuchot

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The aim of this article is to show that the scholastic commentaries on the Predicables or Categorems (in Porphiry Eisagoge) constituted a style of treatises on the philosophy of language and philosophy of logic. In such studies, called afterwards “Material Logic”, is considered, for instance, the theme of the domain of logic and the possibility of its construction; furthermore, logic is relates to ontology through the problem of universals. Here is explored to logical being (ens rationis) which is the objectum (subject) of this discipline, and is analized the structure of proposition and the nature of the main constitutives of inference. In the side of Philosophy of Language are located the study of the meaning of subjects and predicates (or predicables), that of the proposition formed by them, also a hierarchy of logical types (and semantical ones), and the principles of the ordained disposition of natural kinds and other classifications. They are things that now attract the interest of philosophers of logic and philosophers of languagewithin the analytic tradition.
49. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Tobies Grimaltos

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper I offer an interpretation of those paragraphs of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus in which Wittgenstein talks about negative facts. In my opinion we cannot conclude that Wittgenstein held that negative facts have actual existence, as RusselI, for example, did.By means of a kind of journey through several possible interpretations, I arrive to the conclusion that negative facts are nothing but non-effective possibilities; they are in the logical space, in the field of possible worlds, but they have no actual existence, they are not inhabitants of the world. Finally, it is suggested that, insofar as pictures are facts, the only negative facts were, for Wittgenstein, the negative pictures and not what those pictures depict.
50. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
José Hierro S.Pescador

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
51. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Francisco Rodríguez Consuegra

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this article I propose a new explanation of the relationship between Russell and ther first Wittgenstein. There are five main novelties in my interpretation; (i) the use of all relevant unpublished manuscripts of Russell; (ii) the discovery of the first apparition of the “multiple theory of judgment” in a purely logical and unpublished context; (iii) the role of the Bradleian objection against relations in the evolution of the nation of form in both Russell and Wittgenstein; (iv) a general point of view to obtain a common explanation of all the criticisms of Wittgenstein against Russell and of the abandonment to Theory of Knowledge; and (v) the first account of the contribution of Whitehead to the progressive Russellian evolution from atomism to holism.
52. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
A. MantecaAlonso-Cortés

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
53. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Juan A. Nuño

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
54. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Teresa Bejarano

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Self-reference suffices to define performative sentences. “I say (or its variants) that” is communicatively functional. By it, speaker shows he is aware of how he is being seen by hearers. Therefore “I order” and “I do not order” are equally performative, though the latter does not perform any activity. This is our first proposal. In the subdivision (criterion of activity can do nothing but a subdivision), “I do not permit” isactive. Our second proposal explains that anomaly attending to synonymy between “I do not permit” and “I forbid”, but without using it as a premature escape.
55. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Eduardo deBustos

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
56. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Antoni GomilaBenejam

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Katz (1981, 1985) has denied the psychological import of Linguistics on the grounds of alleged inconsistencies that arise when Linguistics is conceived as a psychological enterprise, and proposed an alternative Platonistic conception. The paper discards the plausibility of this latter approach to the study of natural language but recognizes the difficulties Katz has pointed out. It is claimed that these difficulties appear if the “strong competence hypothesis” (Bresnan & Kaplan, 1982) is assumed, that is, if it is assumed that the form of the speaker’s knowledge of language is that of a grammar. A weaker conception of the psychological relevance of linguisitic theories is proposed-one that avoids Katz’s difficulties, is more congenial to Chomsky, and clears the way for a fruitful cooperation between Linguistics and Psycholinguistics.
57. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Edurne Zunzunegui

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper, I assume that speech act theory should be based on a theory of action. I will try to show that a pragmatic theory of speech acts (Gazdar, 1981) can be easily based on a certain theory of action (a model combining Searle’s and Von Wright’s proposals).

seccion ix. logica, metodologia y filosofia de las ciencias juridicas y sociales

58. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Manuel Atienza

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
59. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Albert Calsamiglia

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
60. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1/2/3
Ernesto GarzónValdés

view |  rights & permissions | cited by