Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 61-80 of 441 documents

Show/Hide alternate language

academic life academic life

61. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 3
Ярослав Шрамко, Ірина Хоменко
Yaroslav Shramko
Modern analytic philosophy: historical origins and prospects of development. (Based on the materials of the 11th International Congress of the Society for Analytical Philosophy, September 12-15, 2022, Berlin, Germany)
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Огляд матеріалів ХІ Міжнародного конгресу Німецького товариства аналітичної філо-софії, а також новітніх тенденцій у розвитку аналітичних досліджень

articles articles

62. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Олена Сирцова
Olena Syrtsova
Corpus Areopagiticum: the question of its dependence from Proclus, the hypothesis of Synesius’ authorship, and philosophical terminology of Slavic translations
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The study of the peculiarities of the reception of such an essential concept of the philosoph-ical Corpus Dionysiacum Areopagiticum as ὑπερούσιος in ancient Slavic translations has is promising. It allows not only to understand better the internal perspective of the development of philosophical terminology in Rus’-Ukraine, where in the 15th–17th centuries, there existed a sig-nificant number of manuscripts of the corpus, but also to strengthen the argument in favor of its dating precisely in the 5th century. According to the conceptual features that are present in the Greek text of De divinis nominibus and are confirmed in the studies of Slavic translations of the Corpus Areopagiticum, this work, preserved also in other languages, could belong to an author, who uniquely combined his Christian views and a philosophical vision of the world that was inspired by his Neoplatonic education at the Alexandrian School of Philosophy under the guidance of the eminent Neoplatonic thinker and mathematician Hypatia, who was well acquainted with the ideas of Plotinus and the whole Alexandrian intellectual tradition. It is possible that this author, who used the ideas of Plotinus and Porphyry and for the first time unfolded the idea of the Christian God as the Hyperousios in the aspect of the Christian Triad in his philosophical hymns and treatises, could be Synesius of Cyrene, Bishop of Ptolemais.
63. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Олег Хома
Oleg Khoma
Skeptical expressions in “Outlines of Pyrrhonism” and Descartes’ project of “Meditations on First Philosophy”
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The paper aims to prove the hypothesis that Sextus Empiricus’ Neo-Pyrrhonism is significantly influenced by the Cartesian meditation as a genre of philosophizing. It refutes theses about (1) the non-predicativity of Sextus’ language and about (2) Sextus’ epochê as an automatic result of the action of opposite things or statements, and it argues that both Sextus and Descartes distinguish between (a) internal (forced) agreement with clarity and (b) the personal acceptance of this agreement which depends on a volitional decision. Sextus’ recognition of the clarity of appearance as appearance gives Descartes the only chance to refute the skepticism of Sextus, which is invulnerable to external criticism. Therefore, Descartes developed meditation as a special model of purely immanent criticism (the very word “skepticism” is never mentioned in the Meditations), focused on dealing with states of clarity and evidence. The author’s hypothesis is that the key elements to which this model appeals are the “history of a skeptic” set out in Outlines of Pyrrhonism and the conception of skeptical expressions. This hypothesis can be tested further by proving or disproving the thesis that the discourse of I, II, and at least partially of III Meditations is based on the pattern of skeptical expressions, focused on the internal states of the speaker, and not on clarifying the “objective” state of affairs (i.e. not on dogmatic inferences).
64. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Сергій Секундант
Sergii Secundant
Eugène Dupréel and Chaїm Perelman: the normative and critical principles of the “rhetorical turn” in contemporary philosophy. Part 1
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The purpose of this article is to give a critical assessment of the methodological, epistemological and philosophical principles of the “rhetorical turn” as a historico-philosophical phenomenon in contemporary philosophy. The first part offers a reconstruction and a critical assessment of the methodological and epistemological foundations of Eugène Dupréel's critique of the key features of “classical philosophy”, namely, the concept of necessary knowledge and the concept of progress. These are supplemented by a brief analysis of Chaїm Perelman’s reception of Dupréel's theses in his works of the so-called “turning point” period (1947–1949). It is shown that Dupréel's critique is “axiological” in nature and consists in his reassessment of the principles of classical methodology and epistemology. In his critique of the doctrine of necessary knowledge from the standpoint of humanism, Dupréel wittingly vindicates the methodological and epistemological principles of sophistry (critical realism, subjectivism, pragmatism, pluralism, relativism, conventionalism, etc.), but endows these, as well as other concepts of classical epistemology, with a new, humanistic, meaning. Perelman generally supports the main points of Dupréel's criticism, strengthening their social and humanistic orientation. This article demonstrates that the criticism of classical philosophy offered by both thinkers is limited in terms of both its subject and its principles. After all, it (1) provides a simplified image of “classical philosophy”, (2) is based on a misunderstanding of the fundamentally conceptual and constructive nature of philosophical knowledge, (3) is carried out from the standpoint of “socially oriented realism”, and, therefore, (4) has no bearing on the epistemological principles of idealistic and religious movements,(5) leading to the separation of philosophy from scientific and religious knowledge.

philosophical handbooks philosophical handbooks

65. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Олег Хома
Oleg Khoma
Investigatio
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
66. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Сергій Секундант, Аріна Орєхова
Sergii Secundant
Time and Space in the Philosophy of Leibnitz. Part I
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Arina Orіekhova's interview with Professor Sergii Secundant, devoted to Leibniz's concepts of time and space, the peculiarities of Michael Fatch's interpretation of those concepts, and various historico-philosophical approaches to understanding Leibniz's philosophy as a whole.

reviews reviews

67. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Олександр Луковина
Oleksandr Lukovyna
Defense of Authentic Neo-Pyrrhonism. Smith, P. (2022). Sextus Empiricus’ Neo-Pyrrhonism: Skepticism as a Rationally Ordered Experience. Cham: Springer.
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Review of Smith, P. (2022). Sextus Empiricus’ Neo-Pyrrhonism: Skepticism as a Rationally Ordered Experience. Cham: Springer.
68. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Василь Мацьків
Vasyl Matskiv
Plato in the vice of Nietzsche and Strauss. Lampert, L. (2021). How Socrates Became Socrates. A Study of Plato's Phaedo, Parmenides, and Symposium. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Review of Lampert, L. (2021). How Socrates Became Socrates. A Study of Plato's Phaedo, Parmenides, and Symposium. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

new editions new editions

69. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Андрій Баумейстер, Всеволод Хома
Andrii Baumeister
Capability Approach and its Historico-philosophical Roots. Chiappero-Martinetti, E., Osmani, S., & Qizilbash, M. (Eds.). (2020). The Cambridge Handbook of the Capability Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Review of Chiappero-Martinetti, E., Osmani, S., & Qizilbash, M. (Eds.). (2020). The Cambridge Handbook of the Capability Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
70. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Ілля Давіденко
Illia Davidenko
Reflection of modern Hegel studies. Boldyrev, I., Stein, S. et al. (2021). Interpreting Hegel's Phenomenology of spirit: expositions and critique of contemporary readings. London: Routledge.
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Review of Boldyrev, I., Stein, S. et al. (2021). Interpreting Hegel's Phenomenology of spirit: expositions and critique of contemporary readings. London: Routledge.
71. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Віталій Туренко
Vitali Turenko
New edition of Рresocratic fragments: materials of Herculaneum papyri. Vassallo, C. (2021). The Presocratics at Herculaneum. A Study of Early Greek Philosophy in the Epicurean Tradition. Berlin: De Gruyter.
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Review of Vassallo, C. (2021). The Presocratics at Herculaneum. A Study of Early Greek Philosophy in the Epicurean Tradition. Berlin: De Gruyter.
72. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Михайло Якубович
Mykhaylo Yakubovych
Islam, Creationism and Evolutionism: Theoretical Contempolations. Ahmed Malik, S. (2021). Islam and Evolution: Al-Ghazālī and the Modern Evolutionary Paradigm. London: Routledge.
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Review of Ahmed Malik, S. (2021). Islam and Evolution: Al-Ghazālī and the Modern Evolutionary Paradigm. London: Routledge.

academic life academic life

73. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Анатолій Єрмоленко, Всеволод Хома, Ілля Давіденко, Ксенія Мирошник
Anatoliy Yermolenko
German philosophy in the Ukrainian context (70-80s of the 20th century). Part IІ
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Interview of Vsevolod Khoma, Illia Davidenko and Kseniia Myroshnyk with Anatoliy Yermolenko.
74. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Світлана Іващенко, Ілля Давіденко, Влада Анучіна, Дар’я Попіль
Svitlana Ivashchenko
The Thing: Why I'm an Editor. Part I
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Interview of Illia Davidenko, Vlada Anuchina and Daria Popil with Svitlana Ivashchenko.
75. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Євген Причепій, Влада Анучіна, Яна Горобенко, Яна Дзюба
Yevhen Prychepii
Phenomenology of fate signs. Part I
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Interview of Vlada Anuchina, Yana Dziuba and Yana Gorobenko with Yevhen Prychepii.
76. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Ілля Давіденко
Illia Davidenko
Current State of Researh on the Oral History of Philosophy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Report on the main discussions that took place during the online roundtable “The Oral History of Philosophy: Outlining its Subject” (July 6, 2022).

articles articles

77. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 1
Роман Кисельов Orcid-ID
Roman Kyselov
Reasoning about Plagiarism in Europe before Jacob Thomasius
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper provides an overview of the early considerations regarding the phenomenon of plagiarism – from Greco-Roman antiquity to the time when a thorough study examining literary theft in its textual, legal, and moral manifestations was printed, i. e. “Philosophical Dissertation on Literary Plagiarism” (1673) by Jacob Thomasius. Although the issue of plagiarism was very vital in ancient times, all the oldest considerations concerning the appropriation of other people’s texts were essentially pragmatic moves or reactions rather than purposeful theoretical interpretations of the subject. However, in addition to the situational grounds of the accusation, they can reveal certain principles that, according to estimations of the time, could prevent or refute allegations of plagiarism. It was enough if the author stated, albeit generally but clearly, that the fragments of other people’s texts, whether altered or not, were used. It was also acceptable if the reader believed that the author considered his borrowings recognizable to educated readers. Another reason for the elimination of possible accusations was the factor of competition – the author’s desire to adapt the achievements of another cultural environment in his own one, significantly improving them. The medieval and early modern materials generally testify to the relevance of ancient views and reveal some new problems. This is, in particular, the incompatibility of new more formalized ideas about authorship and traditional educational practices, which encouraged the uncontrolled use of others’ texts. Some authors also emphasized that plagiarism was an obstacle to the development of science. The paper ends with examples that show how European ideas about the rules of using others’ writings may help interpret the writing methods of the early modern Ukrainian authors, including philosophers.
78. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 1
Анна Лактіонова Orcid-ID
Anna Laktionova
Quine, Goodman, Putnam: the Harvard Philosophical School
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This article offers formal and doctrinal reasons that prove the existence of the "Harvard Philosophical School" as a real historico-philosophical phenomenon. The author includes Willard Van Orman Quine, Nelson Goodman, and Hilary Putnam in this school. The aim of this article is to compare the conceptualism, relativism and anti-realism of Quine, Goodman and Pantem, on the basis of (neo)pragmatic tendencies in their philosophical studies. All these philosophers were professors at Harvard University; in addition, Quine was a teacher of Goodman and Putnam, Goodman was a teacher of Putnam. Quine, Goodman, and Putnam, each in his own specific pragmatic way, stood on the positions of relativism, anti-realism, conceptualism, and tried to separate themselves from “cultural relativism”. Common touchstone concepts and tendencies in particular in their philosophical investigations are: conceptual scheme, indeterminacy of translation, internal criteria, ontological relativity and others. The obvious analogy between Quine's standards of similarity, Goodman's standards of correctness, and standards for Putnam's conceptual schemes. The role played in their doctrines by the ideas of William James, who also taught at Harvard, at least hypothetically allows us to expand the boundaries of this school.
79. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 1
Ołena Łucyszyna Orcid-ID
Олена Луцишина
Поняття мовної конвенції (samaya, saṃketa) в індійській думці
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Linguistic convention (samaya/saṃketa) is one of the central notions of Indian philosophy of language. I present a new classification of traditions of Indian thought based on their view of linguistic convention. This classification is to be verified and expanded in further studies. 1) Nyāya, Vaiśeṣika, Buddhism, and later classical Yoga of the Tattvavaiśāradī accept samaya/saṃketa as an agreement initiating the relationship between words and their previously unrelated meanings. 2) Bhartṛhari the Grammarian and the continuators of his thought acknowledge samaya/saṃketa as the established usage of words that is rooted in the natural relationship between words and their meanings; the convention manifests (makes known) the relationship. This view was probably also shared by Mīmāṃsakas and Advaitins. 3) Classical Yoga of the Yogasūtrabhāṣya and probably also earlier Grammar thought of the Mahābhāṣya accept linguistic convention as the established usage of words, but this usage, though having neither a beginning nor an end, is not based on any natural and necessary word–meaning relationship. In this view, linguistic convention not only manifests the word–meaning relationship but also keeps it in existence. Finally, I also explain why the same Sanskrit term samaya/saṃketa was applied to the different ways of understanding linguistic convention. I explain this through the common aspects of all three kinds of samaya/saṃketa. The first aspect is the content of all these kinds of samaya/saṃketa. Irrespective of how linguistic convention is understood, its content is the same: “such and such a word has such and such a meaning”. The second aspect is the crucial role of linguistic convention in language acquisition, communication, and transmission.
80. Sententiae: Volume > 41 > Issue: 1
Анастасія Стрелкова Orcid-ID
Anastasia Strelkova
The Concept of «suffering» in Buddhism: Ontological Problematics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper the philosophical problematics of the ontological dimension of suffering in the Buddhist philosophy is raised. Many modern scholars are inclined to think that a more adequate translation for the Sanskrit term duḥkha is “unsatisfactoriness”. However, from the material presented in the article it follows that this rendering does not underlie the sense of the notion of duḥkha when it is examined in the ontological plane, and thus the traditional translation “suffering” in this sense remains more adequate. It is also shown that the etymology of the Sanskrit term duḥkha as a «improperly installed» axle of the wheel of a cart has strong connotations with the metaphor of the wheel and the symbol of swastika in the Buddhist cultural tradition (wheel of being, three turnings of the Wheel of Dharma etc.). In this paper the main causes of suffering (self, body, ignorance, desire and other afflictions) exposed in Buddhist texts and scholarship are revised, and on the example of the Cūḷasuññata-sutta it is demonstrated that the real final cause of suffering in the Early Buddhism is our body and not our “self” and ignorance. While in the Mahayana Buddhism based on the philosophy of emptiness and the principle of nonduality, the dichotomy of soul and body is removed, the attainment of nirvana becomes possible in this body and the real cause and source of suffering becomes the ignorance. On the other hand, the paper argues that just the ontological view on the problem of suffering (under the angle of the principle of nonduality) provides us with understanding of the fact that the suffering can be overcome despite its indestructible ontological status.