Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 81-100 of 274 documents


political philosophy

81. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 22
Todd May

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

epistemology

82. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 22
Eric Mandelbaum, Jake Quilty-Dunn

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

political philosophy

83. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 22
Andrew Koppelman

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

weakness of will

84. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 22
Agnes Callard

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

phenomenology

85. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 22
Jody Azzouni

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

86. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 22

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

87. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 21
Oliver Cronlinde Wenner

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

ethics

88. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 21
Robert Merrihew Adams

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

philosophy of mind

89. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 21
Alexis Burgess

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

aesthetics

90. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 21
Garry L. Hagberg

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Wittgenstein’s scattered remarks on music, when brought together and then related to his similarly scattered remarks on culture, show a deep and abiding concern with music as a repository and conveyer of meaning in human life. Yet the conception of meaning at work in these remarks is not of a kind that is amenable to brief or concise articulation. This paper explores that conception, considering in turn (a) the relational networks within which musical meaning emerges, (b) what he calls a discernible “kinship” between composers and styles, (c) the embodied character of musical content, (d) the close and too-little-appreciated intricate connections between our capacity to make sense in music and in language (and the frequent dependence of the former on the latter) and the interaction of the musical theme with spoken language, and (e) music as a culturally-embedded phenomenon that is, as he said of language, possible only in what he evocatively, if too briefly, called “the stream of life.”

philosophy of language

91. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 21
Alexander George

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

epistemology

92. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 21
Cora Diamond

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

metaethics

93. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 21
Ayoob Shahmoradi

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

modern european philosophy

94. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 21
Lilian Alweiss

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

political philosophy

95. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 21
Peter Baumann

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper discusses the philosophical view proposed by Gregory Mankiw in his recent article “Defending the One Percent” (JEP 27-3, 2013): the just deserts view in application to income distribution. Mankiw’s view suffers from three unsolved problems: the Criteria Problem, the Measurement Problem, and the Problem of the Missing Desert Function. The overall conclusion is that Mankiw’s normative “Defense of the One Percent” fails quite drastically.

philosophy of literature

96. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 21
Simon Critchley

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

97. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 20
Oliver Cronlinde Wenner

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

lecture

98. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 20
Jonathan Dancy

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

political philosophy

99. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 20
Samuel Scheffler

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

metaphilosophy

100. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 20
Adrian Moore

view |  rights & permissions | cited by